•  225
    Conservativeness and incompleteness
    Journal of Philosophy 80 (9): 521-531. 1983.
  •  90
    Vagueness, Open-Texture, and Retrievability
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 56 (2-3): 307-326. 2013.
    Just about every theorist holds that vague terms are context-sensitive to some extent. What counts as ?tall?, ?rich?, and ?bald? depends on the ambient comparison class, paradigm cases, and/or the like. To take a stock example, a given person might be tall with respect to European entrepreneurs and downright short with respect to professional basketball players. It is also generally agreed that vagueness remains even after comparison class, paradigm cases, etc. are fixed, and so this context sen…Read more
  •  51
    Life on the Ship of Neurath: Mathematics in the Philosophy of Mathematics
    Croatian Journal of Philosophy 26 (2): 11--27. 2012.
    Some central philosophical issues concern the use of mathematics in putatively non-mathematical endeavors. One such endeavor, of course, is philosophy, and the philosophy of mathematics is a key instance of that. The present article provides an idiosyncratic survey of the use of mathematical results to provide support or counter-support to various philosophical programs concerning the foundations of mathematics
  •  18
    Review: Sets and Abstracts: Discussion (review)
    Philosophical Studies 122 (3). 2005.
  •  14
    Arithmetic Sinn and Effectiveness
    Dialectica 38 (1): 3-16. 1984.
    SummaryAccording to Dummett's understanding of Frege, the sense of a denoting expression is a procedure for determining its denotation. The purpose of this article is to pursue this suggestion and develop a semi‐formal interpretation of Fregean sense for the special case of a first‐order language of arithmetic. In particular, we define the sense of each arithmetic expression to be a hypothetical process to determine the denoted number or truth value. The sense‐process is “hypothetical” in that t…Read more
  •  97
    Understanding church's thesis
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 10 (3): 353--65. 1981.
  •  27
    I—Stewart Shapiro
    Supplement to the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 79 (1): 147-165. 2005.
  •  116
    Principles of reflection and second-order logic
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 16 (3). 1987.
  •  37
    Comparing implicit and explicit memory for brand names from advertisements
    with H. Shanker Krishnan
    Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied 2 (2): 147. 1996.
  •  128
    The purpose of this paper is to present a thought experiment and argument that spells trouble for “radical” deflationism concerning meaning and truth such as that advocated by the staunch nominalist Hartry Field. The thought experiment does not sit well with any view that limits a truth predicate to sentences understood by a given speaker or to sentences in (or translatable into) a given language, unless that language is universal. The scenario in question concerns sentences that are not under…Read more
  •  148
    ‘Neo-logicist‘ logic is not epistemically innocent
    with Alan Weir
    Philosophia Mathematica 8 (2): 160--189. 2000.
    The neo-logicist argues tliat standard mathematics can be derived by purely logical means from abstraction principles—such as Hume's Principle— which are held to lie 'epistcmically innocent'. We show that the second-order axiom of comprehension applied to non-instantiated properties and the standard first-order existential instantiation and universal elimination principles are essential for the derivation of key results, specifically a theorem of infinity, but have not been shown to be epistemic…Read more
  •  3
  •  289
    Epistemology of mathematics: What are the questions? What count as answers?
    Philosophical Quarterly 61 (242): 130-150. 2011.
    A paper in this journal by Fraser MacBride, ‘Can Ante Rem Structuralism Solve the Access Problem?’, raises important issues concerning the epistemological goals and burdens of contemporary philosophy of mathematics, and perhaps philosophy of science and other disciplines as well. I use a response to MacBride's paper as a framework for developing a broadly holistic framework for these issues, and I attempt to steer a middle course between reductive foundationalism and extreme naturalistic quietis…Read more
  •  43
    On the notion of effectiveness
    History and Philosophy of Logic 1 (1-2): 209-230. 1980.
    This paper focuses on two notions of effectiveness which are not treated in detail elsewhere. Unlike the standard computability notion, which is a property of functions themselves, both notions of effectiveness are properties of interpreted linguistic presentations of functions. It is shown that effectiveness is epistemically at least as basic as computability in the sense that decisions about computability normally involve judgments concerning effectiveness. There are many occurrences of the pr…Read more
  •  138
  •  131
    Mathematics and philosophy of mathematics
    Philosophia Mathematica 2 (2): 148-160. 1994.
    The purpose of this note is to examine the relationship between the practice of mathematics and the philosophy of mathematics, ontology in particular. One conclusion is that the enterprises are (or should be) closely related, with neither one dominating the other. One cannot 'read off' the correct way to do mathematics from the true ontology, for example, nor can one ‘read off’ the true ontology from mathematics as practiced.
  •  142
    Reasoning with Slippery Predicates
    Studia Logica 90 (3): 313-336. 2008.
    It is a commonplace that the extensions of most, perhaps all, vague predicates vary with such features as comparison class and paradigm and contrasting cases. My view proposes another, more pervasive contextual parameter. Vague predicates exhibit what I call open texture: in some circumstances, competent speakers can go either way in the borderline region. The shifting extension and anti-extensions of vague predicates are tracked by what David Lewis calls the “conversational score”, and are regu…Read more
  •  1
    Book Reviews (review)
    Mind 101 (402): 361-364. 1992.
  •  172
    Vagueness in context
    Oxford University Press. 2006.
    Stewart Shapiro's ambition in Vagueness in Context is to develop a comprehensive account of the meaning, function, and logic of vague terms in an idealized version of a natural language like English. It is a commonplace that the extensions of vague terms vary according to their context: a person can be tall with respect to male accountants and not tall (even short) with respect to professional basketball players. The key feature of Shapiro's account is that the extensions of vague terms also var…Read more
  •  138
    This chapter provides broad coverage of the notion of logical consequence, exploring its modal, semantic, and epistemic aspects. It develops the contrast between proof-theoretic notion of consequence, in terms of deduction, and a model-theoretic approach, in terms of truth-conditions. The main purpose is to relate the formal, technical work in logic to the philosophical concepts that underlie reasoning.
  •  18
    Reflections on Kurt Godel
    Philosophical Review 100 (1): 130. 1991.
  • Anti-realism and modality
    In J. Czermak (ed.), Philosophy of Mathematics, Hölder-pichler-tempsky. pp. 269--287. 1993.
  •  63
    The status of logic
    In Paul Artin Boghossian & Christopher Peacocke (eds.), New Essays on the A Priori, Oxford University Press. pp. 333--366. 2000.
  •  58
    Intentional mathematics (edited book)
    Sole distributors for the U.S.A. and Canada, Elsevier Science Pub. Co.. 1985.
    Among the aims of this book are: - The discussion of some important philosophical issues using the precision of mathematics. - The development of formal systems that contain both classical and constructive components. This allows the study of constructivity in otherwise classical contexts and represents the formalization of important intensional aspects of mathematical practice. - The direct formalization of intensional concepts (such as computability) in a mixed constructive/classical context.
  • Philosophy of Mathematics: Structure and Ontology
    Philosophical Quarterly 50 (198): 120-123. 2000.