•  1
    Vagueness, Metaphysics, and Objectivity
    In Richard Dietz & Sebastiano Moruzzi (eds.), Cuts and Clouds: Vaguenesss, its Nature and its Logic, Oxford University Press. 2010.
  •  33
    Life on the Ship of Neurath
    Croatian Journal of Philosophy 9 (2): 149-166. 2009.
    Some central philosophical issues concern the use of mathematics in putatively non-mathematical endeavors. One such endeavor, of course, is philosophy, and the philosophy of mathematics is a key instance of that. The present article provides an idiosyncratic survey of the use of mathematical results to provide support or counter-support to various philosophical programs concerning the foundations of mathematics.
  •  140
    Structure and identity
    In Fraser MacBride (ed.), Identity and Modality, Oxford University Press. pp. 34--69. 2006.
    According to ante rem structuralism a branch of mathematics, such as arithmetic, is about a structure, or structures, that exist independent of the mathematician, and independent of any systems that exemplify the structure. A structure is a universal of sorts: structure is to exemplified system as property is to object. So ante rem structuralist is a form of ante rem realism concerning universals. Since the appearance of my Philosophy of mathematics: Structure and ontology, a number of crit…Read more
  •  29
    The Work of John Corcoran: An Appreciation
    with Stewart Shapiro and Michael Scanlan
    History and Philosophy of Logic 20 (3-4): 149-158. 1999.
  •  162
    Incompleteness, mechanism, and optimism
    Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 4 (3): 273-302. 1998.
    §1. Overview. Philosophers and mathematicians have drawn lots of conclusions from Gödel's incompleteness theorems, and related results from mathematical logic. Languages, minds, and machines figure prominently in the discussion. Gödel's theorems surely tell us something about these important matters. But what?A descriptive title for this paper would be “Gödel, Lucas, Penrose, Turing, Feferman, Dummett, mechanism, optimism, reflection, and indefinite extensibility”. Adding “God and the Devil” wou…Read more
  •  145
    An “I” for an I: Singular terms, uniqueness, and reference
    Review of Symbolic Logic 5 (3): 380-415. 2012.
    There is an interesting logical/semantic issue with some mathematical languages and theories. In the language of (pure) complex analysis, the two square roots of i’ manage to pick out a unique object? This is perhaps the most prominent example of the phenomenon, but there are some others. The issue is related to matters concerning the use of definite descriptions and singular pronouns, such as donkey anaphora and the problem of indistinguishable participants. Taking a cue from some work in lingu…Read more
  •  28
    The governance of identity
    In Fraser MacBride (ed.), Identity and Modality, Oxford University Press. pp. 164--173. 2006.
  •  87
  •  34
    Philosophy of Mathematics
    In Peter Clark & Katherine Hawley (eds.), Philosophy of Science Today, Oxford University Press Uk. 2003.
    Moving beyond both realist and anti-realist accounts of mathematics, Shapiro articulates a "structuralist" approach, arguing that the subject matter of a mathematical theory is not a fixed domain of numbers that exist independent of each other, but rather is the natural structure, the pattern common to any system of objects that has an initial object and successor relation satisfying the induction principle
  •  229
    The classical continuum without points
    Review of Symbolic Logic 6 (3): 488-512. 2013.
    We develop a point-free construction of the classical one- dimensional continuum, with an interval structure based on mereology and either a weak set theory or logic of plural quantification. In some respects this realizes ideas going back to Aristotle,although, unlike Aristotle, we make free use of classical "actual infinity". Also, in contrast to intuitionistic, Bishop, and smooth infinitesimal analysis, we follow classical analysis in allowing partitioning of our "gunky line" into mutually ex…Read more
  •  58
    Effectiveness
    In Johan van Benthem, Gerhard Heinzman, M. Rebushi & H. Visser (eds.), The Age of Alternative Logics, Springer. pp. 37--49. 2006.
  •  176
    Foundations of Mathematics: Metaphysics, Epistemology, Structure
    Philosophical Quarterly 54 (214). 2004.
    Since virtually every mathematical theory can be interpreted in set theory, the latter is a foundation for mathematics. Whether set theory, as opposed to any of its rivals, is the right foundation for mathematics depends on what a foundation is for. One purpose is philosophical, to provide the metaphysical basis for mathematics. Another is epistemic, to provide the basis of all mathematical knowledge. Another is to serve mathematics, by lending insight into the various fields. Another is to prov…Read more
  •  155
    Mechanism, truth, and Penrose's new argument
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 32 (1): 19-42. 2003.
    Sections 3.16 and 3.23 of Roger Penrose's Shadows of the mind (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1994) contain a subtle and intriguing new argument against mechanism, the thesis that the human mind can be accurately modeled by a Turing machine. The argument, based on the incompleteness theorem, is designed to meet standard objections to the original Lucas-Penrose formulations. The new argument, however, seems to invoke an unrestricted truth predicate (and an unrestricted knowability predicate). I…Read more
  •  243
    It is sometimes said that there are two, competing versions of W. V. O. Quine’s unrelenting empiricism, perhaps divided according to temporal periods of his career. According to one, logic is exempt from, or lies outside the scope of, the attack on the analytic-synthetic distinction. This logic-friendly Quine holds that logical truths and, presumably, logical inferences are analytic in the traditional sense. Logical truths are knowable a priori, and, importantly, they are incorrigible, and so…Read more
  •  24
    Consumer memory for intentions: A prospective memory perspective
    with H. Shanker Krishnan
    Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied 5 (2): 169. 1999.
  •  329
    At the beginning of Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik [1884], Frege observes that “it is in the nature of mathematics to prefer proof, where proof is possible”. This, of course, is true, but thinkers differ on why it is that mathematicians prefer proof. And what of propositions for which no proof is possible? What of axioms? This talk explores various notions of self-evidence, and the role they play in various foundational systems, notably those of Frege and Zermelo. I argue that both programs are u…Read more
  • Mathematics and Objectivity
    In John Polkinghorne (ed.), Meaning in Mathematics, Oxford University Press. 2011.
  •  106
    Set-Theoretic Foundations
    The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 6 183-196. 2000.
    Since virtually every mathematical theory can be interpreted in Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory, it is a foundation for mathematics. There are other foundations, such as alternate set theories, higher-order logic, ramified type theory, and category theory. Whether set theory is the right foundation for mathematics depends on what a foundation is for. One purpose is to provide the ultimate metaphysical basis for mathematics. A second is to assure the basic epistemological coherence of all mathematica…Read more
  •  19
    Vagueness and Logic
    In Giuseppina Ronzitti (ed.), Vagueness: A Guide, Springer Verlag. pp. 55--81. 2011.
  •  1
  •  276
    The Objectivity of Mathematics
    Synthese 156 (2): 337-381. 2007.
    The purpose of this paper is to apply Crispin Wright’s criteria and various axes of objectivity to mathematics. I test the criteria and the objectivity of mathematics against each other. Along the way, various issues concerning general logic and epistemology are encountered.
  •  341
    Identity, indiscernibility, and Ante Rem structuralism: The tale of I and –I
    Philosophia Mathematica 16 (3): 285-309. 2008.
    Some authors have claimed that ante rem structuralism has problems with structures that have indiscernible places. In response, I argue that there is no requirement that mathematical objects be individuated in a non-trivial way. Metaphysical principles and intuitions to the contrary do not stand up to ordinary mathematical practice, which presupposes an identity relation that, in a sense, cannot be defined. In complex analysis, the two square roots of –1 are indiscernible: anything true of one o…Read more
  •  88
    Reasoning, logic and computation
    Philosophia Mathematica 3 (1): 31-51. 1995.
    The idea that logic and reasoning are somehow related goes back to antiquity. It clearly underlies much of the work in logic, as witnessed by the development of computability, and formal and mechanical deductive systems, for example. On the other hand, a platitude is that logic is the study of correct reasoning; and reasoning is cognitive if anything Is. Thus, the relationship between logic, computation, and correct reasoning makes an interesting and historically central case study for mechanism…Read more
  •  60
    Book reviews (review)
    with Ben-Ami Scharfstein, Gary Jason, John Blackmore, R. A. Naulty, and F. Bradford Wallack
    Philosophia 17 (4): 551-570. 1987.
  •  192
    Truth, function and paradox
    Analysis 71 (1): 38-44. 2011.
    Michael Lynch’s Truth as One and Many is a contribution to the large body of philosophical literature on the nature of truth. Within that genre, advocates of truth-as-correspondence, advocates of truth-as-coherence, and the like, all hold that truth has a single underlying metaphysical nature, but they sharply disagree as to what this nature is. Lynch argues that many of these views make good sense of truth attributions for a limited stretch of discourse, but he adds that each of the contenders …Read more