•  35
    The welfare economics of population
    Social Choice and Welfare 2 221-34. 1985.
    Intuition suggests there is no value in adding people to the population if it brings no benefits to people already living: creating people is morally neutral in itself. This paper examines the difficulties of incorporating this intuition into a coherent theory of the value of population. It takes three existing theories within welfare economics - average utilitarianism, relativist utilitarianism, and critical-level utilitarianism - and considers whether they can satisfactorily accommodate the in…Read more
  •  290
    Fairness
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91. 1991.
    John Broome; V*—Fairness, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 91, Issue 1, 1 June 1991, Pages 87–102, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian/91.1.87.
  •  82
    Synchronic requirements and diachronic permissions
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 45 (5-6): 630-646. 2015.
    Reasoning is an activity of ours by which we come to satisfy synchronic requirements of rationality. However, reasoning itself is regulated by diachronic permissions of rationality. For each synchronic requirement there appears to be a corresponding diachronic permission, but the requirements and permissions are not related to each other in a systematic way. It is therefore a puzzle how reasoning according to permissions can systematically bring us to satisfy requirements
  •  319
    Comments on Boghossian
    Philosophical Studies 169 (1): 19-25. 2014.
  •  97
    Reply to Rabinowicz
    Philosophical Issues 19 (1): 412-417. 2009.
    No Abstract
  •  82
  •  43
    Responses
    Philosophical Studies 173 (12): 3431-3448. 2016.
    This is a response to the comments of Boghossian, Cullity, Pettit and Southwood on my book Rationality Through Reasoning.
  •  72
    Should Social Preferences Be Consistent?
    Economics and Philosophy 5 (1): 7. 1989.
    Should social preferences conform to the principles of rationality we normally expect of individuals? Should they, for instance, conform to the consistency axioms of expected utility theory? This article considers one fragment of this question
  •  266
    Normative practical reasoning: John Broome
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 75 (1). 2001.
    Practical reasoning is a process of reasoning that concludes in an intention. One example is reasoning from intending an end to intending what you believe is a necessary means: 'I will leave the next buoy to port; in order to do that I must tack; so I'll tack', where the first and third sentences express intentions and the second sentence a belief. This sort of practical reasoning is supported by a valid logical derivation, and therefore seems uncontrovertible. A more contentious example is norm…Read more
  •  367
    This study uses techniques from economics to illuminate fundamental questions in ethics, particularly in the foundations of utilitarianism. Topics considered include the nature of teleological ethics, the foundations of decision theory, the value of equality and the moral significance of a person's continuing identity through time.
  •  91
    The Public and Private Morality of Climate Change
    The Tanner Lectures on Human Values 32 3-20. 2013.
    The Tanner Lectures are a collection of educational and scientific discussions relating to human values. Conducted by leaders in their fields, the lectures are presented at prestigious educational facilities around the world
  •  125
    Enkrasia
    Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 20 (4): 425-436. 2013.
  •  249
    Reasoning with preferences?
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 59 183-208. 2006.
    Rationality requires certain things of you. It requires you not to have contradictory beliefs or intentions, not to intend something you believe to be impossible, to believe what obviously follows from something you believe, and so on. Its requirements can be expressed using schemata such as
  •  64
    A Reply To My Critics
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 40 (1): 158-171. 2016.
  •  27
    Reply to Jones-Lee
    Economics and Philosophy 23 (3): 385-387. 2007.
    It is not the job of philosophy to give direct practical advice either to people or to governments. Nevertheless, moral philosophy is immensely significant in practical matters. It influences the way we think and act, but only slowly as it filters through the process of public debate. I hope Weighing Lives will have a practical influence, but it is not meant to be a directly practical guide
  •  286
    Requirements
    Hommage À Wlodek; 60 Philosophical Papers Dedicated to Wlodek Rabinowicz. 2007.
    The object of this paper is to explore the intersection of two issues – both of them of considerable interest in their own right. The first concerns the role that feasibility considerations play in constraining normative claims – claims, say, about what we (individually and collectively) ought to do and to be. This issue has particular relevance for the confrontation of moral philosophy with economics (and social science more generally). The second issue concerns whether normative claims are to …Read more
  •  54
    Deontology and Economics
    Economics and Philosophy 8 (2): 269-282. 1992.
    In The Moral Dimension, Amitai Etzioni claims, as did Albert Hirschman in Morality and the Social Sciences, that people often act from moral motives, that economics needs to recognize this, and that it will be significantly changed by doing so. I agree, though I think the changes may be smaller than Etzioni believes – I shall be explaining why. But Etzioni goes further. He makes a specific claim about the sort of morality that motivates people: it is deontological. In this paper, I shall examine…Read more
  •  396
    Motivation
    Theoria 75 (2): 79-99. 2009.
    I develop a scheme for the explanation of rational action. I start from a scheme that may be attributed to Thomas Nagel in The Possibility of Altruism , and develop it step by step to arrive at a sharper and more accurate scheme. The development includes a progressive refinement of the notion of motivation. I end by explaining the role of reasoning within the scheme.
  •  211
    Utilitarianism and expected utility
    Journal of Philosophy 84 (8): 405-422. 1987.
  •  36
    Fairness versus Doing the Most Good
    Hastings Center Report 24 (4): 36-39. 1994.
  •  55
    Trump and Climate Change
    The Philosophers' Magazine 76 22-22. 2017.
  •  461
    Does Rationality Consist in Responding Correctly to Reasons?
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 4 (3): 349-374. 2007.
    Some philosophers think that rationality consists in responding correctly to reasons, or alternatively in responding correctly to beliefs about reasons. This paper considers various possible interpretations of ‘responding correctly to reasons’ and of ‘responding correctly to beliefs about reasons’, and concludes that rationality consists in neither, under any interpretation. It recognizes that, under some interpretations, rationality does entail responding correctly to beliefs about reasons. Tha…Read more
  •  72
    Responses to Setiya, Hussain, and Horty
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 91 (1): 230-242. 2015.
  •  139
    Are intentions reasons? And how should we cope with incommensurable values
    In Christopher W. Morris & Arthur Ripstein (eds.), Practical Rationality and Preference: Essays for David Gauthier, Cambridge University Press. pp. 98--120. 2001.
  •  331
    Reasons and motivation: John Broome
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 71 (1). 1997.
    Derek Parfit takes an externalist and cognitivist view about normative reasons. I shall explore this view and add some arguments that support it. But I shall also raise a doubt about it at the end.
  •  378
    "Utility"
    Economics and Philosophy 7 (1): 1-12. 1991.
    “Utility,” in plain English, means usefulness. In Australia, a ute is a useful vehicle. Jeremy Bentham specialized the meaning to a particular sort of usefulness. “By utility,” he said, “is meant that property in any object, whereby it tends to produce benefit, advantage, pleasure, good, or happiness or to prevent the happening of mischief, pain, evil, or unhappiness to the party whose interest is considered”. The “principle of utility” is the principle that actions are to be judged by their use…Read more
  •  433
    A world climate bank
    with Duncan Foley
    In Axel Gosseries & Iñigo González-Ricoy (eds.), Institutions for Future Generations, Oxford University Press. pp. 156-169. 2016.
  •  860
    Normative requirements
    Ratio 12 (4). 1999.
    Normative requirements are often overlooked, but they are central features of the normative world. Rationality is often thought to consist in acting for reasons, but following normative requirements is also a major part of rationality. In particular, correct reasoning – both theoretical and practical – is governed by normative requirements rather than by reasons. This article explains the nature of normative requirements, and gives examples of their importance. It also describes mistakes that ph…Read more