•  47
    Nietzsche’s View of Truth
    International Studies in Philosophy 19 (2): 3-18. 1987.
  •  44
    This paper introduces phenomenology as a distinctive form of transcendental philosophy by exploring a problem that arises with the phenomenological concept of “constitution,” namely, the “paradox of human subjectivity” – the idea that under the transcendental reduction the human subject is both a entity in the world and the ground of all such constitution. Focusing on the question of what conditions must obtain for something to be the bearer of normatively structured intentional content, the pap…Read more
  •  40
    Taking Maurice Natanson's posthumously published book, The Erotic Bird: Phenomenology in Literature, as its point of departure, the essay argues that "fictive reality" is the specific content of transcendental-phenomenological reflection. Elaborating this concept allows us to see how phenomenological concepts such as constitution, horizon, and the "transcendental" have a tropological, rather than a psychological, meaning. Specifically, the article considers the metonymical structure of reality's…Read more
  •  39
    Logische Untersuchungen Ergänzungsband Erster Teil (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 57 (2): 413-414. 2003.
    By the summer of 1913, Husserl had already completed revisions of the Prolegomena to Pure Logic and the first five Investigations for a new edition of his Logical Investigations. The intervening years had seen considerable development in Husserl’s thought, so he attempted to compromise between a merely mechanical reproduction of the original edition and a complete rewriting from the newly attained standpoint of his transcendental phenomenology. The compromise worked fairly well until Husserl cam…Read more
  •  38
    Gnostic Phenomenology
    New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy 1 257-277. 2001.
  •  38
    Emil Lask: Aletheiology as Ontology
    Kant Studien 87 (1): 69-88. 1996.
  •  31
    Why is Ethics First Philosophy? Levinas in Phenomenological Context
    European Journal of Philosophy 23 (3): 564-588. 2015.
    This paper explores, from a phenomenological perspective, the conditions necessary for the possession of intentional content, i.e., for being intentionally directed toward the world. It argues that Levinas's concept of ethics as first philosophy makes an important contribution to this task. Intentional directedness, as understood here, is normatively structured. Levinas's ‘ethics’ can be understood as a phenomenological account of how our experience of the other subject as another subject takes …Read more
  •  30
    Lask, Heidegger, and the Homelessness of Logic
    Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 23 (3): 222-239. 1992.
  •  29
    Sport as Spectacle and as Play
    International Studies in Philosophy 30 (3): 109-122. 1998.
  •  29
    Interpreting Heidegger. Critical Essays
    Review of Metaphysics 65 (2): 416-418. 2011.
  •  28
    Metaphysics, Metontology, and the End of Being and Time
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (2): 307-331. 2000.
    In 1928 Heidegger argued that the transcendental philosophy he had pursued in Being and Time needed to be completed by what he called “metontology.” This paper analyzes what this notion amounts to. Far from being merely a curiosity of Heidegger scholarship, the place occupied by “metontology” opens onto a general issue concerning the relation between transcendental philosophy and metaphysics, and also between both of these and naturalistic empiricism. I pursue these issues in terms of an ambigui…Read more
  •  28
    Normativity and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger
    Cambridge University Press. 2013.
    Steven Crowell has been for many years a leading voice in debates on twentieth-century European philosophy. This volume presents thirteen recent essays that together provide a systematic account of the relation between meaningful experience and responsiveness to norms. They argue for a new understanding of the philosophical importance of phenomenology, taking the work of Husserl and Heidegger as exemplary, and introducing a conception of phenomenology broad enough to encompass the practices of b…Read more
  •  26
    Rationalism in History
    Diacritics 33 (1): 3-22. 2003.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Diacritics 33.1 (2003) 3-22 [Access article in PDF] Rationalism in History Steven Crowell Mark Bevir. The Logic of the History of Ideas. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1999. [L] When Hegel spoke of history as the "slaughter-bench at which the happiness of peoples, the wisdom of states, and the virtue of individuals have been sacrificed" [27], he wished his hearers to find satisfaction in the contemplation of a "reason" in history that woul…Read more
  •  24
    Robert Scharff's new book wants to set the record straight. For too long, scholars have focused on the topic of Heidegger's thinking, being, and have read Being and Time as a hermeneutic revision of Husserl's transcendental phenomenology, which, like the latter, "takes positions" on philosophical questions, advances "theses," and, for all its emphasis on subjective experience, invites "objective" assessment. Scharff's alternative picture, focused almost exclusively on Heidegger's lecture courses…Read more
  •  23
    In a recent paper1 which critically examines and rejects several suggestions that have been made for “bridging the gap” between Husserl’s phenomenology and neuroscience, Rick Grush concludes on a positive note: It should be obvious enough that while I have been highly critical of van Gelder, Varela and Lloyd, there is a clear sense in which the four of us are on the same team. We all believe that an important source of insights for the task of understanding of mentality is what Lloyd describes a…Read more
  •  21
    Neighbors in Death1
    Research in Phenomenology 27 (1): 208-223. 1997.
  •  21
    If, as many historians and theorists now believe, narrative is the form proper to historical explanation, this raises the problem of the terms in which such narratives are to be evaluated. Without a clear account of evaluation, the status of historical knowledge remains obscure. Beginning with the view, found in Hayden White and others, that historical narrative constitutes a meaning not reducible to the factual content it engages, this essay argues that such meaning can arise only through a syn…Read more
  •  21
    Logic and Ontology in Heidegger (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 22 (1): 146-147. 1990.