•  35
    Causal explanation and the vocabulary of action
    Mind 82 (325): 22-30. 1973.
    It seems plausible to suppose that (a) the vocabulary of action is distinct from and irreducible to that of mere movement, And (b) the causal laws of the natural sciences are couched solely in terms of the latter vocabulary. From these two suppositions, The falsehood of determinism has sometimes been said to follow. I argue that whether this does follow depends on our conception of causal explanation; on the interpretation of this concept that seems to me the most interesting, The falsehood of d…Read more
  • Andrew Woodfield's "Teleology" (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 38 (1): 136. 1977.
  •  30
    Our preferences, ourselves
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 12 (1): 34-50. 1983.
  •  41
    REASON AT WORK is designed for Introduction to Philosophy courses where the instructor prefers to use a collection of readings to introduce the broad divisions of the discipline. This edition includes sixty-two readings organized into the six major branches of philosophical inquiry: Ethics, Social and Political Philosophy, Epistemology, Metaphysics, Philosophy of Religion, and Philosophy of Mind.
  •  32
    Liberal Purposes by William A. Galston (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 90 (1): 49-52. 1993.
  •  124
    Who Knew?: Responsiblity Without Awareness
    Oxford University Press USA. 2009.
    To be responsible for their acts, agents must both perform those acts voluntarily and in some sense know what they are doing. Of these requirements, the voluntariness condition has been much discussed, but the epistemic condition has received far less attention. In Who Knew? George Sher seeks to rectify that imbalance. The book is divided in two halves, the first of which criticizes a popular but inadequate way of understanding the epistemic condition, while the second seeks to develop a more ad…Read more
  •  43
    Groups and justice
    Ethics 87 (2): 174-181. 1977.
  •  69
    Desert
    Princeton University Press. 1987.
    "--Jeffrie Murphy, The Philosophical Review (forthcoming)
  •  93
    Beyond Neutrality: Perfectionism and Politics
    Cambridge University Press. 1997.
    Many people, including many contemporary philosophers, believe that the state has no business trying to improve people's characters, elevating their tastes, or preventing them from living degraded lives. They believe that governments should remain absolutely neutral when it comes to the consideration of competing conceptions of the good. One fundamental aim of George Sher's book is to show that this view is indefensible. A second complementary aim is to articulate a conception of the good that i…Read more
  •  17
    Reasons and intensionality
    Journal of Philosophy 66 (6): 164-168. 1969.
  •  19
    Armstrong on impossible desires
    Philosophical Studies 28 (3). 1975.
  •  22
    Morality Within the Limits of Reason
    Philosophical Review 100 (4): 682. 1991.
  •  423
    Justifying reverse discrimination in employment
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 4 (2): 159-170. 1975.
  •  224
    Three grades of social involvement
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 18 (2): 133-157. 1989.
  • Ethics: essential readings (edited book)
    Routledge. 2012.
  • Critical notices
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (2): 548. 1999.
  •  6
    Review: Educating Citizens (review)
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 18 (1). 1989.
  •  110
    Blameworthy Action and Character
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (2): 381-392. 2002.
    A number of philosophers from Hume on have claimed that it does not make sense to blame people for acting badly unless their bad acts were rooted in their characters. In this paper, I distinguish a stronger and a weaker version of this claim. The claim is false, I argue, if it is taken to mean that agents can only be blamed for bad acts when those acts are manifestations of character paws. However, what is both true and important is the weaker claim that an act is not blameworthy unless it is ro…Read more
  •  63
    Punishment as Societal Defense
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (2): 548-550. 1999.
    Phillip Montague’s point of departure is a simple but illuminating way of conceptualizing the fact that creates the need for punishment—namely, that each society contains some people who will wrongfully kill or injure others unless held in check by a system of penalties. This fact, Montague argues, in effect confronts each society with a forced choice: either allow potential criminals to inflict harm on others, or else prevent them from doing so by maintaining a system of punishment that will ha…Read more
  •  255
    On the decriminalization of drugs
    Criminal Justice Ethics 22 (1): 30-33. 2003.
  •  89
    Moral education and indoctrination
    with William J. Bennett
    Journal of Philosophy 79 (11): 665-677. 1982.
  •  56
    Hare, abortion, and the golden rule
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 6 (2): 185-190. 1977.
  •  69
    Subsidized abortion: Moral rights and moral compromise
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 10 (4): 361-372. 1981.
  •  180
    Diversity
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 28 (2): 85-104. 1999.
  •  14
    Reasons, causes, and clear cases
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 13 (1): 83-88. 1975.