•  5
    Précis
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 73 (3): 309-312. 2015.
  •  8
    Forthcoming in Conference Proceedings, Jena Phänomenologie conference I Hegels Charakterisierungen der neuen, von ihm entwickelten philosophischen Form, der Phänomenologie des Geistes, stellen vor allem deswegen ein Problem dar, weil sie so zahlreich sind. Bei einigen handelt es sich um klar erkennbare Reformulierungen oder Spezifizierungen anderer, in vielen Fällen aber scheinen die Beschreibungen inkonsistent zu sein oder unterschiedliche Perioden in Hegels Denken widerzuspiegeln, das sich wäh…Read more
  •  73
    In the most influential chapter of his most important philosophical work, the Phenomenology of Spirit, Hegel makes the central and disarming assertions that "self-consciousness is desire itself" and that it attains its "satisfaction" only in another self-consciousness. Hegel on Self-Consciousness presents a groundbreaking new interpretation of these revolutionary claims, tracing their roots to Kant's philosophy and demonstrating their continued relevance for contemporary thought. As Robert Pippi…Read more
  •  75
    Nietzsche and the origin of the idea of modernism
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 26 (2). 1983.
    The notion of modernism, originally a classificatory term in art and literary criticism, now a common term of art in many philosophic (and anti?philosophic) programs, has remained an elusive, often vague point of view. For a discussion of the notion's historical accuracy and philosophic legitimacy this article selects an author greatly responsible for setting out the problem (called by him ?nihilism') and philosophically sensitive to the issues involved in claiming that something essential to a …Read more
  •  21
    Nietzsche’s Critique of Causality
    International Studies in Philosophy 18 (2): 17-27. 1986.
  •  188
    The significance of taste: Kant, aesthetic and reflective judgment
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 34 (4): 549-569. 1996.
    The Significance of Taste: Kant, Aesthetic and Reflective Judgment ROBERT B. PIPPIN 1? THE FUNDAMENTAL QUESTION of the "Analytic of the Beautiful" in the "Critique of Aesthetic Judgment" is easy enough to identify. On what basis, if any, could one claim some sort of universal a priori validity for judgments of the form, "This is beautiful"? In Kant's well-known analysis of this question, the issue is reformulated as: By what right could one claim that another person ought to feel pleasure in the…Read more
  •  100
    Hegel's metaphysics and the problem of contradiction
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 16 (3): 301-312. 1978.
  •  72
    Blumenberg and the Modernity Problem
    Review of Metaphysics 40 (3). 1987.
    In the long aftermath of such modernist suspicions about the still dominant "official" Enlightenment culture, the very title of the recently translated book by Hans Blumenberg is a bluntly direct invitation to controversy--The Legitimacy of the Modern Age. For Blumenberg, when Giordano Bruno, condemned to burn at the stake in 1600, defiantly turned his face from a crucifix offered him as a last chance at redemption, the heroic gesture should be seen as just that, heroic and historically decisive…Read more
  • The Erotic Nietzsche: Philosophers without Philosophy
    In Shadi Bartsch & Thomas Bartscherer (eds.), Erotikon: essays on Eros, ancient and modern, University of Chicago Press. pp. 172--91. 2005.
  •  277
    Authenticity in Painting: Remarks on Michael Fried’s Art History
    with Michael Fried, Michel Chaouli, Stefan Andriopoulos, Richard Menke, Carlo Ginzburg, Dragan Kujundzic, Jacques Derrida, and J. Hillis Miller
    Critical Inquiry 31 (3): 575. 2005.
    My topic is authenticity in or perhaps as painting, not the authenticity of paintings; I know next to nothing about the problem of verifying claims of authorship. I am interested in another kind of genuineness and fraudulence, the kind at issue when we say of a person that he or she is false, not genuine, inauthentic, lacks integrity, and, especially when we say he or she is playing to the crowd, playing for effect, or is a poseur. These are not quite moral distinctions (no one has a duty to be a…Read more
  •  39
    Response to David Kolb
    The Owl of Minerva 30 (2): 277-286. 1999.
  •  44
    Hegel and Institutional Rationality
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 39 (S1): 1-25. 2001.
  •  48
    Introduction: Scientific History
    with Susanne Hoeber Rudolph
    In his inaugural lecture at Cambridge as Regius Professor of Modern History in 1895, Lord Acton urged that the historian deliver moral judgments on the figures of his research. Acton declaimed: I exhort you never to debase the moral currency or to lower the standard of rectitude, but to try others by the final maxim that governs your own lives and to suffer no man and no cause to escape the undying penalty which history has the power to inflict on wrong.1 In 1902, the year after Acton died, the …Read more
  •  126
    Philosophy is its own time comprehended in thought
    Topoi 25 (1-2): 85-90. 2006.
    So much philosophy is so unavoidably guided by intuitions, and such intuitions are so formed by examples, and such examples must of necessity present so cropped and abstract a picture of an instance or event or decision, that, left to its traditional methods, philosophy might be ill-equipped on its own to answer a question about the true content of an historical ideal like ``autonomy'', or authenticity or ``leading a free life''. One needs to bring so many factors into play at once that one non-…Read more
  • Hosle, System And Subject
    Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain 17 5-19. 1988.
  • Nietzsche: Thus Spoke Zarathustra (edited book)
    with Adrian Del Caro
    Cambridge University Press. 2006.
    Nietzsche regarded 'Thus Spoke Zarathustra' as his most important work, and his story of the wandering Zarathustra has had enormous influence on subsequent culture. Nietzsche uses a mixture of homilies, parables, epigrams and dreams to introduce some of his most striking doctrines, including the Overman, nihilism, and the eternal return of the same. This edition offers a new translation by Adrian Del Caro which restores the original versification of Nietzsche's text and captures its poetic brill…Read more
  •  46
    Doer and Deed: Responses to Acampora and Anderson
    Journal of Nietzsche Studies 44 (2): 181-195. 2013.
    I am very grateful to both commentators for these thoughtful and stimulating questions and remarks and especially for the care and generous charity animating their summations of the position I defend in the book. That has not always been the case in discussions of the book.Both critics rightly note the importance of the French moralistes in my attempt to understand why Nietzsche should have said that “psychology” might now (that is, for him) become once again the “queen of the sciences” and so o…Read more
  •  117
    Hegel’s Original Insight
    International Philosophical Quarterly 33 (3): 285-295. 1993.
  •  76
    Medical Practice and Social Authority
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 21 (4): 417-437. 1996.
    Questions of medical ethics are often treated as especially difficult casuistical problems or as difficult cases illustrative of paradoxes or advantages in global moral theories. I argue here, in opposition to such approaches, for the inseparability of questions of social history and social theory from any normative assessment of medical practices. The focus of the discussion is the question of the legitimacy of the social authority exercised by physicians, and the insufficiency of traditional d…Read more
  •  7
    Bernard Williams once made the interesting point that both Wittgenstein and Nietzsche were trying to say something about what it might mean for philosophy to come to an end, for a culture to be cured of philosophy. He meant the end of philosophical theory, the idea that unaided human reason could contribute to knowledge about substance, being, our conceptual scheme, the highest values, the meaning of history or the way language works. For both Wittgenstein and Nietzsche there is no good or modes…Read more
  •  35
    American Memory in Henry James: Void and Value
    Common Knowledge 14 (1): 168-168. 2008.