• Experiences of value
    In Charles R. Pigden (ed.), Hume on Motivation and Virtue, Palgrave-macmillan. pp. 121. 2009.
  •  33
    Reasons from Within (review)
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 9 (3): 473-476. 2012.
  •  458
    What Do we See in Museums?
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 79 217-240. 2016.
    I address two related questions. First: what value is there in visiting a museum and becoming acquainted with the objects on display? For art museums the answer seems obvious: we go to experience valuable works of art, and experiencing valuable works of art is itself valuable. In this paper I focus on non-art museums, and while these may house aesthetically valuable objects, that is not their primary purpose, and at least some of the objects they house might not be particularly aesthetically val…Read more
  •  73
    What's wrong?: applied ethicists and their critics (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2004.
    What's Wrong?: Applied Ethicists and Their Critics is a thorough and engaging introduction to applied ethics that covers virtually all of the issues in the field. Featuring more than ninety-five articles, it addresses standard topics--such as abortion, euthanasia, capital punishment, world hunger, and animal rights--and also delves into cutting-edge areas like cloning, racial profiling, same-sex marriage, prostitution, and slave reparations. The volume includes seminal essays by prominent philos…Read more
  •  19
    The Unity of Theories
    In Fred D'Agostino & I. C. Jarvie (eds.), Freedom and Rationality, Reidel. pp. 343--368. 1989.
  •  3
    The moral case for the legalization of voluntary euthanasia
    Victoria University of Wellington Law Review 28 207-24. 1998.
  • Pavel Tichý
    A Companion to Philosophy in Australia and New Zealand. 2010.
  • Control, consequence and compatibilism
    In T. Childers (ed.), Between Words and Worlds, Filosofia. pp. 143-56. 2000.
  •  265
    Conditionalization, cogency, and cognitive value
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48 (4): 533-541. 1997.
    Why should a Bayesian bother performing an experiment, one the result of which might well upset his own favored credence function? The Ramsey-Good theorem provides a decision theoretic answer. Provided you base your decision on expected utility, and the the experiment is cost-free, performing the experiment and then choosing has at least as much expected utility as choosing without further ado. Furthermore, doing the experiment is strictly preferable just in case at least one possible outcome …Read more
  •  38
    The core of the truthmaker research program is that true propositions are made true by appropriate parts of the actual world. This idea seems to give realists their best shot at capturing a robust account of the dependence of truth on the world. For a part of the world to be a truthmaker for a particular it must suffice for, or necessitate, the truth of the proposition. There are two extreme and unsatisfactory truthmaker theories. At one extreme any part of the world (up to and including the who…Read more
  •  64
    Verisimilitude reviewed
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 32 (3): 237-265. 1981.
  •  67
    The aesthetic adequacy of copies
    with David Ward
    British Journal of Aesthetics 29 (3): 258-260. 1989.
  •  12
    Is Science Progressive (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38 (2): 272-276. 1987.
  •  139
    Harmony, purity, truth
    Mind 103 (412): 451-472. 1994.
    David Lewis has argued against the thesis he calls "Desire as Belief", claiming it is incompatible with the fundamentals of evidential decision theory. I show that the argument is unsound, and demonstrate that a version of desire as belief is compatible with a version of causal decision theory.
  •  58
    Ability and Freedom
    with Pavel Tichy
    American Philosophical Quarterly 20 (2). 1983.
  • A decision theoretic argument against human embryo experimentation
    In M. Fricke (ed.), Essays in honor of Bob Durrant, University of Otago Press. pp. 111-27. 1986.
  •  147
    An objectivist's guide to subjective value
    Ethics 102 (3): 512-533. 1992.