•  98
    The harm of immorality
    Ratio 21 (3): 241-259. 2008.
    A central problem in moral theory is how it is to be defended against those who think that there is no harm in being immoral, and that immorality can be in one's self-interest, assuming the perpetrator is not caught and punished. The argument presented here defends the idea that being immoral prevents one from having self-respect. If it makes sense to think that one cannot be happy without self-respect, then the conclusion follows that one cannot be both immoral and happy. Immorality is harmful …Read more
  •  94
    Of Goodness and Healthiness: A Viable Moral Ontology
    Philosophical Studies 87 (3): 309-332. 1997.
  •  84
    Good To Be Bad?
    Think 14 (40): 51-55. 2015.
  •  128
    The Rules of "Goodness": An Essay on Moral Semantics
    American Philosophical Quarterly 40 (3). 2003.
  •  52
    Review: David Wong: Natural Moralities (review)
    Mind 118 (469): 225-230. 2009.
  •  1687
    Morality is necessary for happiness
    Philosophical Studies 174 (10): 2613-2628. 2017.
    An argument for the eponymous conclusion is given through a series of hypothetical syllogisms, the most basic of which is as follows: morality is necessary for self-respect; self-respect is necessary for happiness; therefore, morality is necessary for happiness. Some of the most obvious objections are entertained and rejected.
  •  16
    Partially Re‐Humanized Ethics: Comments on Butchvarov
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1): 184-189. 2003.
  •  19
    Well-Being: Happiness in a Worthwhile Life (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 69 (3): 613-614. 2016.
  •  66
    The Moral Skeptic, by Anita M. Superson (review)
    Mind 120 (479): 914-917. 2011.
  •  13
    Opening questions, following rules
    In Terry Horgan & Mark Timmons (eds.), Metaethics After Moore, Oxford University Press. pp. 169. 2006.
  •  141
    Is There Moral High Ground?
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (4): 511-526. 2003.
  •  44
    Undeniably, life is unfair. So, why play fairly in an unfair world? The answer comes from combining the ancient Greek conception of happiness with a modern conception of self-respect. The book is about why it is bad to be bad and good to be good, and what happens in between.
  •  33
    Review: The Evolution of Morality (review)
    Mind 116 (461): 176-180. 2007.
  •  585
    Moral Point of View (2nd ed.)
    In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, Blackwell. 2013.
  •  79
    Dennett's misremenberings
    Philosophia 26 (1-2): 207-218. 1998.
  •  38
    Why it's bad to be bad
    In Morality and Self-Interest, Oxford University Press. 2008.
    The question “Why is it bad to be bad?” might seem either tautologous or poorly formed. It may seem like a tautology because it seems logical to think that badness is necessarily bad and so it must, of course, follow that it is bad to be bad. It might seem to be malformed because it may seem like anyone who asks the question, “Why is it bad to be bad?” must fail to understand the meaning of the words they are using: generally, if something is X, it cannot fail to be X. If so, then it may seem as…Read more
  •  39
    The Normative Web (review)
    Social Theory and Practice 36 (1): 157-164. 2010.
  •  145
    Prescriptions Are Assertions: An Essay on Moral Syntax
    American Philosophical Quarterly 35 (1). 1998.