St Andrews, FIfe, United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland
  •  46
    Necessity and Deliberation: An Argument from De Interpretatione 9
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (2). 1987.
    In De Interpretatione 9 Aristotle considers the proposition that everything that is or comes to be, is or comes to be of necessity. From the supposition that this is so, he draws the following consequence: ‘[In that case] there would be no need to deliberate or take trouble, [saying] that if we do this there will be so and so, and if we do not do this there will not be so and so’. Finding this result absurd, he rejects the supposition and concludes that some events or states of affairs are conti…Read more
  •  45
    Alternative World-Histories
    Philosophical Papers 31 (2): 117-143. 2002.
    Abstract We act so as to make things better than they would have been but for the action; we are horrified by an uncontrollable catastrophe because it made things so much worse than they would have been without it. Such attitudes are reasonable only if it is reasonable to make the associated counterfactual conditional judgments. But making such judgments cannot be reasonable if one holds both (1) that this world is absolutely and uniquely actual (?absolute actualism?), and (2) that everything is…Read more
  •  42
    Aristotle Through Lenses from Bernard Williams
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 78 23-35. 2016.
    This paper looks at a theme in ancient Greek ethics from perspectives developed by Bernard Williams.1 The ancient theme is the place of theoretical activity in human life, and I shall be referring to Aristotle. Williams is relevant through one strand in his scepticism about ‘morality, the peculiar institution’.2 His discussion suggests questions not merely about Aristotle but ones it would be interesting to put to Aristotle and see how he would or should respond to them.
  •  41
    3 The Sophists and Socrates
    In D. N. Sedley (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Greek and Roman Philosophy, Cambridge University Press. pp. 73. 2003.
  •  35
    The Virtures of Aristotle
    with D. S. Hutchinson
    Philosophical Review 98 (3): 396. 1989.
  •  33
    The Creation of the World
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 78 (1). 2004.
    Part 1 examines the roles of (a) intelligent cause, (b) empirical materials (fire, earth etc.), and (c) the resulting cosmos, in the account of world-making in the Timaeus. It is argued that the presence of (b) is essential for the distinctness of (a) and (c); and an explanation is proposed for why the biblical idea of creation faces no such problem. Part II shows how different suggestions implicit in Plato's doctrine of the intelligible model give rise to radically different kinds of Platonic m…Read more
  •  33
    'Actual Instead'
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 113 (1pt1): 1-19. 2013.
    It is argued that acceptance of determinism sits badly with the way we use counterfactual conditionals when considering gains and losses in light of how things would have been if such-and-such had or had not happened; it is further suggested that one type of indeterminism runs into the same difficulty; also that the difficulty may escape notice through failure to distinguish different uses of counterfactuals.
  •  30
    Plato's Sun-Like Good: Dialectic in the Republic
    Cambridge University Press. 2021.
    Plato's Sun-Like Good is a revolutionary discussion of the Republic's philosopher-rulers, their dialectic, and their relation to the form of the good. With detailed arguments Sarah Broadie explains how, if we think of the form of the good as 'interrogative', we can re-conceive those central reference-points of Platonism in down-to-earth terms without loss to our sense of Plato's philosophical greatness. The book's main aims are: first, to show how for Plato the form of the good is of practical v…Read more
  •  28
    Finding the Mean, Theory and Practice in Aristotelian Political Philosophy (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 25 (3): 145-146. 1993.
  •  21
  •  21
    Corporeal gods, with Reference to Plato and Aristotle
    In Thomas Buchheim & David Meißner (eds.), SOMA: Körperkonzepte und körperliche Existenz in der antiken Philosophie und Literatur, Felix Meiner Verlag. pp. 159-182. 2016.
  •  19
    Aristotle's Perceptual Realism
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 31 (S1): 137-159. 1993.
  •  19
    The Ancient Greeks
    In Helen Beebee, Christopher Hitchcock & Peter Menzies (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Causation, Oxford University Press. 2009.
    There are various motives for refining the notion of cause. Aristotle's was an interest in providing the most informative and illuminating method of explaining the central natural phenomena of his universe. A different sort of motive is created by problems of free will and responsibility, of which readers may have been reminded by the reference to indeterminism. The thought that our free and responsible behaviour is caused by factors over which we have no control has often seemed impossible to a…Read more
  •  19
    Mathematics in Plato's Republic
    Marquette University Press. 2020.
    A discussion of Plato's evaluation of mathematics as an intellectual discipline, and his reasons for training his philosopher-rulers to be mathematical experts.
  •  17
    I-‘Actual Instead’
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 113 (1pt1): 1-19. 2013.
    It is argued that acceptance of determinism sits badly with the way we use counterfactual conditionals when considering gains and losses in light of how things would have been if such‐and‐such had or had not happened; it is further suggested that one type of indeterminism runs into the same difficulty; also that the difficulty may escape notice through failure to distinguish different uses of counterfactuals.
  •  13
    Editorial Note
    Philosophical Quarterly 71 (4). 2021.
  •  10
    Chapter Seven
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 3 (1): 229-252. 1987.
  •  8
    La chance et les biens moraux et non moraux chez Aristote
    Les Etudes Philosophiques 138 (3): 49-63. 2021.
    Le sujet de l’étude est la relation entre le bonheur et la chance selon Aristote. Ce problème est abordé à partir de la question de savoir si la sagesse et la vertu suffisent au bonheur. Si tel était le cas, une personne pauvre et malade serait heureuse. Pour Aristote, au contraire, le bonheur nécessite des biens non moraux pour être complet. Le bonheur n’est pas seulement ce qui rend les autres choses bonnes, il est aussi ce qui est complet et désirable. Dans ce cas, la question du rapport du b…Read more
  •  7
    Heavenly Bodies and First Causes
    In Georgios Anagnostopoulos (ed.), A Companion to Aristotle, Wiley‐blackwell. 2009.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Notes Bibliography.
  •  6
    Listening to Reason in Plato and Aristotle
    Mind 132 (527): 828-833. 2021.
    When we are in a rational frame of mind we are ready to listen to reason (tautology). But if we are not in a rational frame of mind, how does reason (in this ca.
  •  4
    The Virtues of Aristotle (review)
    Philosophical Review 98 (3): 396-398. 1989.
  •  3
    A powerful and appealing explanatory scheme which succeeds on the whole in drawing together a great many seemingly disparate elements in the Physics' into a neat unitary structure.' Canadian Philosophical Reviews.
  •  3
    On the Idea of the Summum Bonum
    In Christopher Gill (ed.), Virtue, norms, and objectivity: issues in ancient and modern ethics, Oxford University Press. pp. 41-58. 2005.