•  51
    Historical Anti-Realism
    The Monist 74 (2): 230-239. 1991.
    In “Narrative Explanations: The Case of History,” Paul A. Roth attempts to defend the legitimacy of narrative explanation in history against two central objections—the “methodological” and the “metaphysical.” Like Roth, I find the category of narrative explanation acceptable even if it is problematic, and even if the notions of “narrative,” “explanation,” and “narrative explanation” are not altogether clear. The philosophically grounded “methodological” objections to narrative explanation are of…Read more
  •  47
    Revisionism Gone Awry: Since When Hasn't Hume Been a Sceptic?
    Journal of Scottish Philosophy 18 (2): 133-155. 2020.
    In this paper, we argue that revisionary theories about the nature and extent of Hume's scepticism are mistaken. We claim that the source of Hume's pervasive scepticism is his empiricism. As earlier readings of Hume's Treatise claim, Hume was a sceptic – and a radical one. Our position faces one enormous problem. How is it possible to square Hume's claims about normative reasoning with his radical scepticism? Despite the fact that Hume thinks that causal reasoning is irrational, he explicitly cl…Read more
  •  46
    Believing Badly
    with Damian Cox
    Philosophical Papers 33 (3): 309-328. 2004.
    This paper explores the grounds upon which moral judgment of a person's beliefs is properly made. The beliefs in question are non-moral beliefs and the objects of moral judgment are individual instances of believing. We argue that instances of believing may be morally wrong on any of three distinct grounds: (i) by constituting a moral hazard, (ii) by being the result of immoral inquiry, or (iii) by arising from vicious inner processes of belief formation. On this way of articulating the basis of…Read more
  •  46
    Swinburne's heaven: One hell of a place: Michael Levine
    Religious Studies 29 (4): 519-531. 1993.
    Discussions of immortality have tended to focus on the nature of personal identity and, in a related way, the mind/body problem. Who is that is going to survive, and is it possible to survive bodily destruction? There has been far less discussion of what immortality would be like; e.g. the nature of heaven. Richard Swinburne, however, has recently discussed ‘heaven’, and has constructed a novel theodicy fundamentally based on his conception of what heaven is like. I shall criticize both his conc…Read more
  •  45
    More on “does traditional theism entail pantheism?”
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 20 (1). 1986.
  •  44
    Pantheism, Ethics and Ecology
    Environmental Values 3 (2). 1994.
    Pantheism is a metaphysical and religious position. Broadly defined it is the view that (1) "God is everything and everything is God ... the world is either identical with God or in some way a self-expression of his nature" (H.P. Owen). Similarly, it is the view that (2) everything that exists constitutes a 'unity' and this all-inclusive unity is in some sense divine (A. MacIntyre). I begin with an account of what the pantheist's ethical position is formally likely to be (e.g. objectivist etc.).…Read more
  •  44
    Introduction: Ethics and architecture
    with Kristine Miller and William Taylor
    Philosophical Forum 35 (2). 2004.
  •  43
    Cartesian Materialism and Conservation: Berkelean Immaterialism?
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 24 (2): 247-259. 1986.
  •  43
    Welcome to Su: the spectral university
    with Damian Cox
    Angelaki 21 (2): 213-226
    While some may argue that universities are in a state of crisis, others claim that we are living in a post-university era; a time after universities. If there was a battle for the survival of the institution it is over and done with. The buildings still stand. Students enrol and may attend lectures, though most do not. But virtually nothing real remains. What some mistakenly take to be a university is, in actuality, an “uncanny” spectral presence. The encompassing ethico-philosophical question i…Read more
  •  41
    Robinson on Berkeley
    Idealistic Studies 22 (2): 163-178. 1992.
  •  41
    Mackie's Account of Necessity in Causation
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 87. 1987.
    Michael P. Levine; V*—Mackie's Account of Necessity in Causation, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 87, Issue 1, 1 June 1987, Pages 75–90, https:/
  •  40
    Book reviews (review)
    with Reinhardt Grossmann
    Philosophia 16 (3-4): 101-109. 1986.
  •  39
    In The Existence of God Richard Swinburne argues that ‘if there is a God, any experience which seems to be of God, will be genuine – will be of God.’ On the face of it this claim of the essential veridicality of any religious experience, given the existence of God, is incredible. Consider what is being claimed by looking at a particularly dramatic example – but one that is well within the purview of Swinburne's claim. The ‘Yorkshire Ripper’ who murdered at least thirteen women, claimed to hear v…Read more
  •  36
    In this paper I dispute Eliot Deutsch's claim [See Deutsch, Eliot (1996) Self-deception: a comparative study, in: Roger T. Ames and Wimal Dissanayake (Eds) Self and Deception: a cross-cultural enquiry (Albany, State University of New York Press), pp. 315-326] that examining self-deception from the perspective of non-Western traditions (i.e. how it is understood in those cultures) can help us to better understand the nature of the phenomenon in one's own culture. Although the claim appears to be …Read more
  •  33
    Response to Commentators: ‘Does Comparative Philosophy Have a Fusion Future?’
    Journal of World Philosophies 2 (1): 174-178. 2017.
    Mark Siderits, Michael Nylan and Martin Verhoeven were invited to respond to Michael Levine’s discussion paper ‘Does Comparative Philosophy Have a Fusion Future?’ This paper documents Levine’s reply to their responses.
  •  32
    7 Avatar: Racism and Prejudice on Pandora
    with Damian Cox
    In Dan Flory & Mary Bloodsworth-Lugo (eds.), Race, Philosophy, and Film, Routledge. pp. 50--117. 2013.
  •  31
    Two theses are central to foundationalism. First, the foundationalist claims that there is a class of propositions, a class of empirical contingent beliefs, that are ‘immediately justified’. Alternatively, one can describe these beliefs as ‘self–evident’, ‘non–inferentially justified’, or ‘self–warranted’, though these are not always regarded as entailing one another. The justification or epistemic warrant for these beliefs is not derived from other justified beliefs through inductive evidential…Read more
  •  31
    Can We Speak Literally of God?
    Religious Studies 21 (1). 1985.
  •  31
    Through various applications of the ‘deep structure’ of moral and religious reasoning, I have sought to illustrate the value of a morally informed approach in helping us to understand the complexity of religious thought and practice…religions are primarily moved by rational moral concerns and…ethical theory provides the single most powerful methodology for understanding religious belief. Ronald Green, Religion and Moral Reason
  •  31
    V*—Mackie's Account of Necessity in Causation
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 87 (1): 75-90. 1987.
    Michael P. Levine; V*—Mackie's Account of Necessity in Causation, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 87, Issue 1, 1 June 1987, Pages 75–90, https:/
  •  30
    Transcendence in theism and pantheism
    Sophia 31 (3): 89-123. 1992.
  •  30
    Some necessary connection theorists maintain that an analysis of causation requires some kind of sui generis metaphysical modal notion such as physical or nomic necessary. However, among necessary connection theorists there are some who argue that the causal connection is not properly understood as merely “physical” or irreducibly “nomic,” but as one of logical entailment. A cause logically entails its effect. Prominent among these theorists have been idealists such as Brand Blanshard.
  •  29
    Why does the paradox play such a crucial role in Kierkegaard's notion of truth as subjectivity? Richard Schacht explains it as follows: Eternal happiness is possible for a man only if it is possible for him to relate himself to God. A man, however, is a being who exists in time; and it would not be possible for such a being to enter into a ‘God-relationship’ if God had not also at some point existed in time. Through the ‘leap of faith’ in which one affirms the proposition that God did exist in t…Read more
  •  27
    ‘Can we speak literally of God?’: MICHAEL P. LEVINE
    Religious Studies 21 (1): 53-59. 1985.
    I shall argue that the question ‘Can we speak literally of God?’ is fundamentally an epistemological question concerning whether we can know that God exists. If and only if we can know that God can exist can we know that we can speak literally of God
  •  26
  •  25
    Museums and the Nostalgic Self
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 79 77-94. 2016.
    The first part of this essay asks: What is the function, purpose and value of a museum? Has any museologist or philosopher given a credible account of philosophical problems associated with museums? Is there any set of properties shared by the diverse entities called museums? Overgeneralization is the principal problem here. The essay then examines a central kind of museum experience; one that invokes and relies upon nostalgia. I argue that the attraction of museums are varied but are best expla…Read more