•  41
    Pragmatism is the idea that philosophical concepts must start with, and remain linked to human experience and inquiry. This book traces and assesses the influence of American pragmatism on British philosophy, with emphasis on Cambridge in the inter-war period, post-war Oxford, and recent developments.
  •  41
    Reply to Four Instructive Critics
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 49 (3): 434. 2013.
    Allow me to begin by thanking Alex Klein, Bjorn Ramberg, Alan Richardson, and Robert Talisse for providing such an excellent set of commentaries on The American Pragmatists, as well as Henry Jackman, for organizing the session at the Canadian Philosophical Association meetings that provided the first forum for the discussion. In this response, I will speak to the general meta-philosophical questions posed by the four commentators, as well as to the more local challenges set to me.All the authors…Read more
  •  41
    Truth and Objectivity (review)
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (3): 365-379. 1992.
  •  40
    Pragmatism and the Transcendental Turn in Truth and Ethics
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 30 (4). 1994.
  •  39
    How Not to Think of Convergence on the Truth
    Modern Schoolman 76 (2-3): 133-140. 1999.
  •  39
    Williams, Pragmatism, and the Law
    Res Publica 27 (2): 155-170. 2020.
    This paper views Bernard Williams through the lens of the pragmatist tradition. The central insight of pragmatism is that philosophy must start with human practice, in contrast to high theory or metaphysics. Williams was one of the twentieth century’s most able proponents of this insight, especially when considering the topics of ethics and the law. Williams never saw himself as a pragmatist, because he took Richard Rorty’s radical relativism to be the exemplar of the position. But I shall sugge…Read more
  •  38
    Rescher and Objective Pragmatism
    Contemporary Pragmatism 2 (2): 25-33. 2005.
    Nicholas Rescher embraces a more objectivist, realist, analytic pragmatism than the pragmatism which has been in vogue in the last two decades. He rejects any pragmatism for which there is no truth, reality, or objectivity but only conversations or solidarity within this or that vocabulary. Rescher has argued that pragmatism, far from being anti-realist, provides the only good argument for realism and for our ability to operate the causal model of inquiry about the real world. I examine this kin…Read more
  •  35
    Review of T. L. short, Peirce's Theory of Signs (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2007 (7). 2007.
  •  34
    Ramsey's Cognitivism: Truth, Ethics and the Meaning of Life
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 78 251-263. 2016.
    Frank Ramsey is usually taken to be an emotivist or an expressivist about the good: he is usually taken to bifurcate inquiry into fact-stating and non-fact stating domains, ethics falling into the latter. In this paper I shall argue that whatever the very young Ramsey's view might have been, towards the end of his short life, he was coming to a through-going and objective pragmatism about all our beliefs, including those about the good, beauty, and even the meaning of life. Ethical beliefs are n…Read more
  •  32
    A Culture of Justification: The Pragmatist’s Epistemic Argument for Democracy
    Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology 5 (1): 94-105. 2008.
  •  31
    Ramsey, Pragmatism, and the Vienna Circle
    European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 11 (1). 2019.
    Frank Ramsey (1903-1930) is usually taken to be sympathetic to the Vienna Circle’s project. I will argue that this is not right. Ramsey was a pragmatist, and he put pragmatist objections to Wittgenstein’s Tractatus, objections which also had the Vienna Circle as their target. Ramsey thought the Circle’s position (like Wittgenstein’s) was mistaken in that, instead of starting with human inquiry, it tried to construct the world out of elementary particulars and logic, and resulted in an unacceptab…Read more
  •  31
    There Can Be No Difference Anywhere that Doesn't Make a Difference Elsewhere
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 54 (3): 417. 2018.
    My title is of course drawn from William James's Pragmatism: A New Name for some Old Ways of Thinking. The five excellent critics of Cambridge Pragmatism: From Peirce and James to Ramsey and Wittgenstein have zeroed in on the profound questions at the heart of pragmatism. All of us working in the tradition should thank them, and I happily do so. In what follows, I will explore the supposed differences between their views and my own. I hope to persuade my critics that sometimes there is no differ…Read more
  •  30
    Language and Experience for Pragmatism
    European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 6 (2). 2014.
    It is sometimes said that contemporary pragmatists place too much emphasis on language and not enough on experience. This objection might hold for the pragmatism of Richard Rorty and his students, but it does not hold for the pragmatism of C. S. Peirce, William James, and John Dewey. I shall argue that we should return to the classical pragmatists and their truth-and-experience position. Indeed, an important insight at the very heart of pragmatism is that language and experience cannot be pulled…Read more
  •  29
    William H. Newton-Smith (1943–2023)
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 35 (2): 205-208. 2023.
    William (Bill) Newton-Smith was a renowned Canadian philosopher of science who spent his career largely in Oxford and then at the Central European University in Hungary.Newton-Smith was born in Ori...
  •  28
    In the preface to this excellent book, Fraser MacBride says he decided to write it because he had "become convinced that there is far more to find out and far more to learn from the history of early analytic philosophy". He is right; the history of early analytic philosophy holds insights for us today, and most of them lie outside of what MacBride calls our "cartoon histories." In punchy prose, he mines gems from what one of his heroes, Frank Ramsey, called "that great muddle the theory of unive…Read more
  •  27
    Narrative evidence and evidence‐based medicine
    Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 16 (2): 392-397. 2010.
  •  25
    Richardson on the construction of moral norms
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 106 (1): 251-256. 2023.
  •  24
    Truth and the End of Inquiry: A Peircean Account of Truth
    with John Boler
    Philosophical Review 102 (1): 110. 1993.
  •  24
    Cheryl Misak offers a strikingly new view of the development of philosophy in the twentieth century. Pragmatism, the home-grown philosophy of America, thinks of truth not as a static relation between a sentence and the believer-independent world, but rather, a belief that works. The founders of pragmatism, Peirce and James, developed this idea in more and less objective ways. The standard story of the reception of American pragmatism in England is that Russell and Moore savaged James's theory, a…Read more
  •  23
  •  21
    Steven Methven, Frank Ramsey and the Realistic Spirit
    Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 7 (6). 2019.
    Reviewed by Cheryl Misak.
  •  20
    There are few finalities in philosophy. No one sees this as sharply as David Wiggins, who is always refining and improving his views. Here he has revised and re.
  •  18
    Life After the Storm: Surviving COVID-19
    Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 63 (3): 494-501. 2020.
    Critical care medicine is suddenly, and unfortunately, in the news, with staggering numbers of COVID-19 patients requiring treatment in intensive care units around the world. Talk on the street, in those countries in which talk on the street is allowed, is of ventilators, ARDS, and cytokine storms—the overcharged immune response that itself is a killer. These technical terms are now in everyday use, and questions that have been restricted largely to critical care, infectious diseases, and public…Read more
  •  18
    _Verificationism_ is the first comprehensive history of a concept that dominated philosophy and scientific methodology between the 1930s and the 1960s. The verificationist principle - the concept that a belief with no connection to experience is spurious - is the most sophisticated version of empiricism. More flexible ideas of verification are now being rehabilitated by a number of philosophers. C.J. Misak surveys the precursors, the main proponents and the rehabilitators. Unlike traditional stu…Read more
  •  16
    Frank Ramsey: A Sheer Excess of Powers
    Oxford University Press. 2020.
    Frank Ramsey was a brilliant Cambridge philosopher, mathematician, and economist who died in 1930 at 26 having made landmark contributions to decision theory, game theory, mathematics, logic, semantics, philosophy of science, and the theory of truth. This rich biography tells the story of his extraordinary life and intellectual achievement.
  •  16
    Pragmatism and deflationism
    In New Pragmatists, Oxford University Press. pp. 68--90. 2007.
  •  14
    Critical Notice
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (3): 365-379. 1992.
  •  14
    Grace de Laguna: American pragmatist
    Asian Journal of Philosophy 2 (2): 1-9. 2023.
    This paper explores the under-recognized Grace de Laguna’s relationship to the tradition of American pragmatism, the tradition that was dominant in her time and place and the emerging tradition of analytic philosophy. It argues that while de Laguna mounted some challenges to pragmatism, they do not hit their mark and while de Laguna at times distanced herself from pragmatism, she ought to be seen as part of that tradition, as well as part of the tradition of analytic philosophy.
  •  14
  •  13
    Making Disagreement Matter
    In Robert B. Talisse & Scott F. Aikin (eds.), The Pragmatism Reader: From Peirce Through the Present, Princeton University Press. pp. 471-484. 2011.