•  1
    Causation and Reduction
    In Helen Beebee, Christopher Hitchcock & Peter Menzies (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Causation, Oxford University Press. 2009.
  •  2
    Wesley Salmon provided three classic criteria of adequacy for satisfactory interpretations of probability. A fourth criterion is suggested here. A distinction is drawn between frequency-driven probability models and theory-driven probability models and it is argued that single case accounts of chance are superior to frequency accounts at least for the latter. Finally it is suggested that theories of chance should be required only to be contingently true, a position which is a natural extension o…Read more
  •  78
    Speculative Ontology
    In Don Ross, James Ladyman & Harold Kincaid (eds.), Scientific metaphysics, Oxford University Press. pp. 51. 2013.
  •  34
    This chapter contains sections titled: Why Use Mathematical Models? Theory‐based Models Data‐based Modeling Computational Approaches Conclusions Notes.
  •  6
    Observation and Reliable Detection
    In Maria Luisa Dalla Chiara (ed.), Language, Quantum, Music, . pp. 19--24. 1999.
  •  21
    Scientific knowledge
    In M. Sintonen, J. Wolenski & I. Niiniluoto (eds.), Handbook of Epistemology, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 549--569. 2004.
  •  28
    Network Epistemology
    Episteme 6 (2): 221-229. 2009.
  •  30
    Letters to the Editor
    with J. B. Schneewind, Leonard Katz, Celia Wolf-Devine, George Graham, Daniel P. Anderson, Mary Ellen Waithe, Tibor R. Machan, and Jonathan E. Adler
    Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 69 (5). 1996.
  •  26
    Review: The Grand Leap (review)
    with David Freedman
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47 (1). 1996.
  •  21
    Conceptual Sea Changes
    Spontaneous Generations 4 (1): 111-115. 2010.
    The reshaping of much scientific research around computational methods is not just a technological curiosity. It results in a significant reshaping of conceptual and representational resources within science in ways with which many traditional philosophical positions are ill-equipped to cope. Some illustrations of this are provided and a consequence for the roles of science and the arts is noted
  •  44
    Self‐Assembling Systems
    Philosophy of Science 73 (5): 595-604. 2006.
    Starting with the view that methodological constraints depend upon the nature of the system investigated, a tripartite division between theoretical, semitheoretical, and empirical discoveries is made. Many nanosystems can only be investigated semitheoretically or empirically, and this aspect leads to some nanophenomena being weakly emergent. Self-assembling systems are used as an example, their existence suggesting that the class of systems that is not Kim-reducible may be quite large.
  •  119
    Network Epistemology
    Episteme 6 (2): 221-229. 2009.
    A comparison is made between some epistemological issues arising in computer networks and standard features of social epistemology. A definition of knowledge for computational devices is provided and the topics of nonconceptual content and testimony are discussed
  •  124
    Computational models
    Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science Association 2002 (3). 2002.
    A different way of thinking about how the sciences are organized is suggested by the use of cross‐disciplinary computational methods as the organizing unit of science, here called computational templates. The structure of computational models is articulated using the concepts of construction assumptions and correction sets. The existence of these features indicates that certain conventionalist views are incorrect, in particular it suggests that computational models come with an interpretation th…Read more
  •  4
    Book reviews (review)
    Mind 101 (402): 390-395. 1992.
  •  185
    Some considerations on conditional chances
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55 (4): 667-680. 2004.
    Four interpretations of single-case conditional propensities are described and it is shown that for each a version of what has been called ‘Humphreys' Paradox’ remains, despite the clarifying work of Gillies, McCurdy and Miller. This entails that propensities cannot be a satisfactory interpretation of standard probability theory. Introduction The basic issue The formal paradox Values of conditional propensities Interpretations of propensities McCurdy's response Miller's response Other possibilit…Read more
  •  21
    Publisher's note
    with Ryszard Wójcicki
    Foundations of Science 1 (3): 1-1. 1995.
    As Chinese Studies in Philosophy enters its twenty-fifth year, we wish to thank the editor since its inception, Professor Cheng Chung-ying of the University of Hawaii, for his many years of service, and to welcome with this issue our new editor, Professor Michael Schoenhals of Stockholm University
  •  83
    Computational empiricism
    Foundations of Science 1 (1): 119-130. 1995.
    I argue here for a number of ways that modern computational science requires a change in the way we represent the relationship between theory and applications. It requires a switch away from logical reconstruction of theories in order to take surface mathematical syntax seriously. In addition, syntactically different versions of the same theory have important differences for applications, and this shows that the semantic account of theories is inappropriate for some purposes. I also argue agains…Read more
  •  74
    Wesley Salmon provided three classic criteria of adequacy for satisfactory interpretations of probability. A fourth criterion is suggested here. A distinction is drawn between frequency‐driven probability models and theory‐driven probability models and it is argued that single case accounts of chance are superior to frequency accounts at least for the latter. Finally it is suggested that theories of chance should be required only to be contingently true, a position which is a natural extension o…Read more
  •  417
    How properties emerge
    Philosophy of Science 64 (1): 1-17. 1997.
    A framework for representing a specific kind of emergent property instance is given. A solution to a generalized version of the exclusion argument is then provided and it is shown that upwards and downwards causation is unproblematical for that kind of emergence. One real example of this kind of emergence is briefly described and the suggestion made that emergence may be more common than current opinions allow
  •  256
    Synchronic and diachronic emergence
    Minds and Machines 18 (4): 431-442. 2008.
    I discuss here a number of different kinds of diachronic emergence, noting that they differ in important ways from synchronic conceptions. I argue that Bedau’s weak emergence has an essentially historical aspect, in that there can be two indistinguishable states, one of which is weakly emergent, the other of which is not. As a consequence, weak emergence is about tokens, not types, of states. I conclude by examining the question of whether the concept of weak emergence is too weak and note that …Read more
  •  112
    Computational science and scientific method
    Minds and Machines 5 (4): 499-512. 1995.
    The process of constructing mathematical models is examined and a case made that the construction process is an integral part of the justification for the model. The role of heuristics in testing and modifying models is described and some consequences for scientific methodology are drawn out. Three different ways of constructing the same model are detailed to demonstrate the claims made here.
  •  20
    Models as mediators: perspectives on natural and social science
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 33 (2): 374-377. 2002.
  •  104
    Are there algorithms that discover causal structure?
    with David Freedman
    Synthese 121 (1-2): 29-54. 1999.
    There have been many efforts to infer causation from association byusing statistical models. Algorithms for automating this processare a more recent innovation. In Humphreys and Freedman[(1996) British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47, 113–123] we showed that one such approach, by Spirtes et al., was fatally flawed. Here we put our arguments in a broader context and reply to Korb and Wallace [(1997) British Journal for thePhilosophy of Science 48, 543–553] and to Spirtes et al.[(1997) Br…Read more
  •  443
    Reasons are given to justify the claim that computer simulations and computational science constitute a distinctively new set of scientific methods and that these methods introduce new issues in the philosophy of science. These issues are both epistemological and methodological in kind.
  •  61
    Data Analysis: Models or Techniques? (review)
    Foundations of Science 18 (3): 579-581. 2013.
    In this commentary to Napoletani et al. (Found Sci 16:1–20, 2011), we argue that the approach the authors adopt suggests that neural nets are mathematical techniques rather than models of cognitive processing, that the general approach dates as far back as Ptolemy, and that applied mathematics is more than simply applying results from pure mathematics