Cornell University
Sage School of Philosophy
PhD, 1977
CV
Charlottesville, Virginia, United States of America
Areas of Interest
History of Western Philosophy
  •  29
    Consent and Fairness in Planning Land Use
    Business and Professional Ethics Journal 6 (2): 5-19. 1987.
  •  190
    An essay on the modern state
    Philosophical Review 109 (2): 271-273. 2000.
    This important book is the first serious philosophical examination of the modern state. It inquires into the justification of this particular form of political society. It asks whether all states are "nation-states," what are the alternative ways of organizing society, and which conditions make a state legitimate. The author concludes that, while states can be legitimate, they typically fail to have the powers (e.g., sovereignty) they claim. Many books analyze government and its functions, but n…Read more
  •  2
    Justification and Legitimacy: Essays on Rights and Obligations
    Law and Philosophy 22 (2): 195-216. 2003.
    A. John Simmons is widely regarded as one of the most innovative and creative of today's political philosophers. His work on political obligation is regarded as definitive and he is also internationally respected as an interpreter of John Locke. The characteristic features of clear argumentation and careful scholarship that have been hallmarks of his philosophy are everywhere evident in this collection. The essays focus on the problems of political obligation and state legitimacy as well as on h…Read more
  •  26
    Democracy’s Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy
    Philosophical Review 107 (1): 133. 1998.
    As its subtitle indicates, Democracy’s Discontent is a study of the political philosophies that have guided America’s public life. The “search” Michael Sandel describes has, in his view, temporarily come to a disappointing resolution in America’s acceptance of a liberal “public philosophy” that “cannot secure the liberty it promises” and has left Americans “discontented” with their “loss of self-government and the erosion of community”. This theme is unlikely to surprise readers familiar with Sa…Read more
  •  2
    A Duty to Obey the Law: For or Against?
    with Christopher Heath Wellman
    Law and Philosophy 28 (1): 101-107. 2009.
  •  199
    Associative political obligations
    Ethics 106 (2): 247-273. 1996.
    It is claimed by philosophers as diverse as Burke, Walzer, Dworkin, and MacIntyre that our political obligations are best understood as "associative" or "communal" obligations--that is, as obligations that require neither voluntary undertaking nor justification by "external" moral principles, but rather as "local" moral responsibilities whose normative weight derives entirely from their assignment by social practice. This paper identifies three primary lines of argument that appear to support su…Read more
  •  17
    Reasonable Expectations and Obligations: A Reply to Postow
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 19 (1): 123-127. 1981.
  •  355
    Moral Principles and Political Obligations
    Princeton University Press. 1979.
    Every political theorist will need this book . . . . It is more 'important' than 90% of the work published in philosophy."--Joel Feinberg, University of Arizona.
  •  686
    Ideal and nonideal theory
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 38 (1): 5-36. 2010.
    No Abstract
  •  146
    “Denisons” and “Aliens”: Locke's Problem of Political Consent
    Social Theory and Practice 24 (2): 161-182. 1998.
    Locke appears to be committed to the peculiar views that native-born residents and visiting aliens have the same political status (since both are tacit consenters) and that real political societies have very few "members" with full rights and duties (since only express consenters seem to be counted as "members"). Locke, however, also subscribes to a principle governing our understanding of the content of vague or inexplicit consent: such consent is consent to all and only that which is necessary…Read more
  •  50
    The Limits of Lockean Rights in Property (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (4): 997-999. 1998.
  •  38
    On the Territorial Rights of States 1
    Philosophical Issues 11 (1): 300-326. 2001.
  •  6
    Justification and Legitimacy: Essays on Rights and Obligations (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 2000.
    A. John Simmons is widely regarded as one of the most innovative and creative of today's political philosophers. His work on political obligation is regarded as definitive and he is also internationally respected as an interpreter of John Locke. The characteristic features of clear argumentation and careful scholarship that have been hallmarks of his philosophy are everywhere evident in this collection. The essays focus on the problems of political obligation and state legitimacy as well as on h…Read more
  •  119
    External justifications and institutional roles
    Journal of Philosophy 93 (1): 28-36. 1996.
    In his paper "Role Obligations," Michael Hardimon defends an account of the nature and justification of institutional obligations that he takes to be clearly superior to the "standard" voluntarist view. Hardimon argues that this standard view presents a "misleading and distorted" picture of role obligations (and of morality generally); and in its best form he claims this view still "leaves out" of its understanding of even contractual role obligations an "absolutely vital factor". I argue agains…Read more
  •  217
    Is There a Duty to Obey the Law?
    Cambridge University Press. 2005.
    The central question in political philosophy is whether political states have the right to coerce their constituents and whether citizens have a moral duty to obey the commands of their state. In this 2005 book, Christopher Heath Wellman and A. John Simmons defend opposing answers to this question. Wellman bases his argument on samaritan obligations to perform easy rescues, arguing that each of us has a moral duty to obey the law as his or her fair share of the communal samaritan chore of rescui…Read more
  •  8
    Bentham
    Philosophical Review 87 (4): 610. 1978.
  •  16
    Social Justice
    Philosophical Review 86 (4): 590. 1977.
  •  95
    Makers' rights
    The Journal of Ethics 2 (3): 197-218. 1998.
    This paper examines the thesis that human labor creates property rights in or from previously unowned objects by virtue of labor's power to make new things. This thesis is considered for two possible roles: first, as a thesis to which John Locke might have been committed in his writings on property; and second, as a thesis of independent plausibility that could serve as part of a defensible contemporary theory of property rights. Understanding Locke as committed to the thesis of makers' rights h…Read more
  •  100
    Inalienable rights and Locke's treatises
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 12 (3): 175-204. 1983.
  •  138
    Democratic Authority and the Boundary Problem
    Ratio Juris 26 (3): 326-357. 2013.
    Theories of political authority divide naturally into those that locate the source of states' authority in the history of states' interactions with their subjects and those that locate it in structural (or functional) features of states (such as the justice of their basic institutions). This paper argues that purely structuralist theories of political authority (such as those defended by Kant, Rawls, and contemporary “democratic Kantians”) must fail because of their inability to solve the bounda…Read more
  •  68
    The Lockean Theory of Rights
    Princeton University Press. 2020.
    John Locke's political theory has been the subject of many detailed treatments by philosophers and political scientists. But The Lockean Theory of Rights is the first systematic, full-length study of Locke's theory of rights and of its potential for making genuine contributions to contemporary debates about rights and their place in political philosophy. Given that the rights of persons are the central moral concept at work in Locke's and Lockean political philosophy, such a study is long overdu…Read more
  •  52
    On the Edge of Anarchy: Locke, Consent, and the Limits of Society
    Philosophical Review 106 (1): 139. 1997.
    In On the Edge of Anarchy, A. John Simmons simultaneously pursues two distinguishable ends: to defend an interpretation of Locke as a “pure consent” theorist the essence of whose theory is that only actual voluntary individual consent can ground political obligations and authority, and to defend pure consent theory as the best theory of political obligation. Both ends are pursued under the heading of justifying “Lockean” consent theory, and the arguments for them overlap considerably because mos…Read more
  •  27
    Right and Wrong
    Philosophical Review 90 (1): 125. 1981.
  •  501
    Philosophical anarchism
    In Social Science Research Network, Cambridge University Press. 2001.
    Anarchist political philosophers normally include in their theories (or implicitly rely upon) a vision of a social life very different than the life experienced by most persons today. Theirs is a vision of autonomous, noncoercive, productive interaction among equals, liberated from and without need for distinctively political institutions, such as formal legal systems or governments or the state. This "positive" part of anarchist theories, this vision of the good social life, will be discussed o…Read more
  •  16
  •  35