Madison, Wisconsin, United States of America
  •  115
    Group risks, risks to groups, and group engagement in genetics research
    Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 17 (4): 351-369. 2007.
    : This essay distinguishes between two kinds of group harms: harms to individuals in virtue of their membership in groups and harms to "structured" groups that have a continuing existence, an organization, and interests of their own. Genetic research creates risks of causing both kinds of group harms, and engagement with the groups at risk can help to mitigate those harms. The two kinds of group harms call for different kinds of group engagement
  •  30
    Preference, Value, Choice, and Welfare
    Cambridge University Press. 2011.
    This book is about preferences, principally as they figure in economics. It also explores their uses in everyday language and action, how they are understood in psychology and how they figure in philosophical reflection on action and morality. The book clarifies and for the most part defends the way in which economists invoke preferences to explain, predict and assess behavior and outcomes. Hausman argues, however, that the predictions and explanations economists offer rely on theories of prefer…Read more
  • Book Review (review)
    Economics and Philosophy 15 (2): 289-295. 1999.
  •  75
    People have thought about economics for as long as they have thought about how to manage their households, and indeed Aristotle assimilated the study of the economic affairs of a city to the study of the management of a household. During the two millennia between Aristotle and Adam Smith, one finds reflections concerning economic problems mainly in the context of discussions of moral or policy questions. For example, scholastic philosophers commented on money and interest in inquiries concerning…Read more
  •  203
    Are markets morally free zones?
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 18 (4): 317-333. 1989.
    Markets are central institutions in societies such as ours, and it seems appropriate to ask whether markets treat individuals justly or unjustly and whether choices individuals make concerning their market behavior are just or unjust. After all, markets influence most important features of our lives from the environment in which we live to the ways in which we find pleasure and fulfillment. Within market life we collectively determine the shape of human existence.<1>.
  • Defending Microeconomic Theory
    Philosophical Forum 15 (4): 392. 1984.
  • No Title available: Reviews
    Economics and Philosophy 15 (2): 289-295. 1999.
  •  38
    The Composition of Economic Causes
    The Monist 78 (3): 295-307. 1995.
    Discusses the composition of economic causes. Applications of John Stuart Mill’s inductive method to economics; Problems with the deductive method; Effect of multiple causal factors in economics; Derivation of economic laws; Mill’s arguments for deductive economics.
  •  81
    Causal priority
    Noûs 18 (2): 261-279. 1984.
  •  186
    Revealed preference, belief, and game theory
    Economics and Philosophy 16 (1): 99-115. 2000.
    The notion of ‘revealed preference’ is unclear and should be abandoned. Defenders of the theory of revealed preference have misinterpreted legitimate concerns about the testability of economics as the demand that economists eschew reference to (unobservable) subjective states. As attempts to apply revealed-preference theory to game theory illustrate with particular vividness, this demand is mistaken.
  •  56
    Making Interpersonal Comparisons Coherently
    with Martin Barrett
    Economics and Philosophy 6 (2): 293. 1990.
    Many ethical theories, including in particular consequentialist moral the ories, require comparisons of the amount of good possessed or received by different people. In the case of some goods, such as monetary income, wealth, education, or health, such comparisons are relatively unproblematic. Even in the case of such goods there may be serious empirical measurement problems, but there appear to be no difficulties in principle. Thus Cooter and Rappoport maintained that there was no serious diffi…Read more
  •  114
    Health, Naturalism, and Functional Efficiency
    Philosophy of Science 79 (4): 519-541. 2012.
    This essay develops an account of health, the functional efficiency theory, which derives from Christopher Boorse's biostatistical theory. Like the BST, the functional efficiency theory is a nonevaluative view of health, but unlike the BST, it argues that the fundamental theoretical task is to distinguish levels of efficiency with which the parts and processes within organisms and within systems within organisms function. Which of these to label as healthy or pathological is of secondary importa…Read more
  •  29
    Rationality and Knavery
    Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 5 67-79. 1998.
    This paper makes a modest point. Suppose one wants to evaluate alternative policies, institutions or even constitutions on the basis of their consequences. To do so, one needs to evaluate their consequences and one needs to know what their consequences are. Let us suppose that the role of economic theories and game theory in particular is mainly to help us to use information we already possess or that we can acquire at a reasonable cost to judge what the consequences will be. We do not necessari…Read more
  •  1
    Causal Asymmetries
    Mind 109 (436): 933-937. 2000.
  •  165
    Equality versus priority: A misleading distinction
    Economics and Philosophy 31 (2): 229-238. 2015.
    People condemn inequalities for many reasons. For example, many who have no concern with distribution per se criticize inequalities in health care, because these inequalities lessen the benefits provided by the resources that are devoted to health care. Others who place no intrinsic value on distribution believe that a just society must show a special concern for those who are worst off. Some people, on the other hand, do place an intrinsic value on equality of distribution, regardless of its co…Read more
  •  99
    Benevolence, justice, well-being and the health gradient
    Public Health Ethics 2 (3): 235-243. 2009.
    The health gradient among those who are by historical standards both remarkably healthy and well-off is of considerable moral importance with respect to benevolence, justice and the theory of welfare. Indeed it may help us to realize that for most people the good life lies in close and intricate social ties with others which can flourish only when inequalities are limited. The health gradient suggests that there is a story to be told in which egalitarian justice, solidarity, health and well-bein…Read more
  •  63
    No doubt men are capable even now of much more unselfish service than they generally render; and the supreme aim of the economist is to discover how this latent social asset can be developed more quickly and turned to account more wisely. (Alfred Marshall, Principles of Economics , p. 8).
  •  62
    Economics as Separate and Inexact
    Economics and Philosophy 12 (2): 207-220. 1996.
    The Inexact and Separate Science of Economics offers an overview of standard microeconomics and general equilibrium theory. These are not the whole of orthodox economics, and orthodox economics is not the whole of economics. But orthodox economics dominates the profession, and the theoretical core of microeconomics and general equilibrium theory – what I called ‘equilibrium theory’ – is central to most orthodox economics. Unlike many methodological works, which focus almost exclusively on the em…Read more
  •  21
    Philosophy and Economic Methodology
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1984. 1984.
    This paper is concerned with the puzzling divorce that exists between writing on economic methodology and work by philosophers of science. After documenting the extent and nature of the separation and making some disparaging comments about the quality of much of the literature on economic methodology, this essay argues that the divorce results from the differences between the aims of philosophers of science, who are concerned to learn about knowledge acquisition in disciplines such as economics,…Read more
  •  39
    The Deductive Method
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 15 (1): 372-388. 1990.
  •  60
    Critical studies / book reviews
    Philosophia Mathematica 11 (3): 354-358. 2003.
  •  115
    Manipulation and the causal Markov condition
    Philosophy of Science 71 (5): 846-856. 2004.
    This paper explores the relationship between a manipulability conception of causation and the causal Markov condition (CM). We argue that violations of CM also violate widely shared expectations—implicit in the manipulability conception—having to do with the absence of spontaneous correlations. They also violate expectations concerning the connection between independence or dependence relationships in the presence and absence of interventions.
  •  62
    Causal and Explanatory Asymmetry
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1982 (Volume One: Contributed Papers). 1982.
    This paper asks why causal asymmetries should give rise to explanatory asymmetries. One way to give some rationale for the asymmetries of causal explanation is to adopt a pragmatic view of explanation and to stress the fact that causes can be used to manipulate their effects. This paper argues, however, that when one recognizes that causal asymmetry is fundamentally an asymmetry of "connectedness", one can see how causal asymmetry leads to an objective difference between explanations in terms of…Read more
  •  179
    John Stuart mill's philosophy of economics
    Philosophy of Science 48 (3): 363-385. 1981.
    John Stuart Mill regards economics as an inexact and separate science which employs a deductive method. This paper analyzes and restates Mill's views and considers whether they help one to understand philosophical peculiarities of contemporary microeconomic theory. The author concludes that it is philosophically enlightening to interpret microeconomics as an inexact and separate science, but that Mill's notion of a deductive method has only a little to contribute.