University of Pittsburgh
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1972
CV
New Haven, Connecticut, United States of America
  •  66
    Rational Agent, Rational Act
    Philosophical Topics 14 (2): 33-57. 1986.
  •  63
    Valuing Activity
    Social Philosophy and Policy 16 (1): 176. 1999.
    Call the proposition that the good life consists of excellent, distinctively human activity the Aristotelian Thesis. I think of a photograph I clipped from the New York Times as vividly depicting this claim. It shows a pianist, David Golub, accompanying two vocalists, Victoria Livengood and Erie Mills, at a tribute for Marilyn Home. All three artists are in fine form, exercising themselves at the height of their powers. The reason I saved the photo, however, is Mr. Golub's face. He is positively…Read more
  •  61
    Equal Freedom: selected Tanner lectures on human values
    University of Michigan Press. 1995.
    Issues at the major fault-line of political beliefs and debates.
  •  59
    Pleasure as Ultimate Good in Sidgwick’s Ethics
    The Monist 58 (3): 475-489. 1974.
    The notion of pleasure lies at the very heart of Sidgwick’s moral philosophy. For Sidgwick holds not merely that pleasure is a good, but that ultimately it is the only good. And hence it is the good of pleasure which grounds his utilitarianism.
  •  57
    How should ethics relate to (the rest of) philosophy? : Moore's legacy
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1): 1-20. 2003.
  •  55
    Reply to Feldman, Hurka, and Rosati (review)
    Philosophical Studies 130 (3). 2006.
  •  54
    Desires, Reasons, and Causes
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67 (2): 436-443. 2003.
    Jonathan Dancy’s Practical Reality makes a significant contribution to clarifying the relationship between desire and reasons for acting, both the normative reasons we seek in deliberation and the motivating reasons we cite in explanation. About the former, Dancy argues that, not only are normative reasons not all grounded in desires, but, more radically, the fact that one desires something is never itself a normative reason. And he argues that desires fail to figure in motivating reasons also, …Read more
  •  53
    Under Moore's Spell
    Utilitas 10 (3): 286. 1998.
    As David Wiggins points out, although Ross is best known for opposing Moore's consequentialism, Ross comes very close to capitulation to Moore when he accepts, as required by beneficence, a prima facie duty to maximize the good. I argue that what lies behind this is Ross's acceptance of Moore's doctrine of agent-neutral intrinsic value, a notion that is not required by, but is indeed is in tension with, beneficence as doing good to or for others
  •  50
    Reply to Schapiro, smith/strabbing, and Yaffe (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81 (1): 253-264. 2010.
  •  50
    Deontology (edited book)
    Wiley-Blackwell. 2003.
    _ Deontology_ brings together some of the most significant philosophical work on ethics, presenting canonical essays on core questions in moral philosophy. Edited and introduced by Stephen Darwall, these readings are essential for anyone interested in normative theory. With a helpful introduction by Stephen Darwall, examines key topics in deontological moral theory. Includes seven essays which respond to the classic sources. Includes classic excerpts by key figures such Kant, Richard Price and W…Read more
  •  49
    Review of Skorupski's Ethical Explorations (review)
    Utilitas 14 (1): 113. 2002.
  •  49
    Respect, Concern, and Membership
    In Hans Bernhard Schmid, Christoph Henning & Dieter Thomä (eds.), Social Capital, Social Identities: From Ownership to Belonging, De Gruyter. pp. 93-104. 2014.
  •  47
    The inventions of autonomy
    European Journal of Philosophy 7 (3). 1999.
    Book reviewed in this article:J.B. Schneewind, The Invention of Autonomy: A History of Modern Moral Philosophy
  •  47
    Scheffler on Morality and Ideals of the Person
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 12 (2). 1982.
    Scheffler's paper divides into two parts. In the first, he argues that Parfit's argument from the complex view of personal identity neither can, nor is intended to, establish any moral theory; in particular, it cannot establish utilitarianism. Rather, Parfit's aim must have been simply to weaken our attachment to non-utilitarian theories. In discovering that the only philosophically respectable view of personal identity holds it to consist simply in bodily or psychological continuities and conne…Read more
  •  44
    On Sterba’s Argument from Rationality to Morality
    The Journal of Ethics 18 (3): 243-252. 2014.
    James Sterba argues for morality as a principled compromise between self-regarding and other-regarding reasons and that either egoists or altruists, who always give overriding weight to self-regarding and other-reasons, respectively, can be shown to beg the question against morality. He concludes that moral conduct is “rationally required.” Sterba’s dialectic assumes that both egoists and altruists accept that both self-regarding and other-regarding considerations are genuine pro tanto reasons, …Read more
  •  43
    Morality and Principle
    In David Bakhurst, Margaret Olivia Little & Brad Hooker (eds.), Thinking about reasons: themes from the philosophy of Jonathan Dancy, Oxford University Press. pp. 168. 2013.
  •  42
  •  42
    On Schiffer’s Desires
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 17 (2): 193-198. 1979.
  •  42
    The Wages of Contempt
    Emotion Review 15 (3): 168-177. 2023.
    This article analyzes the wages (costs) of contempt. It argues that the social and political division and dysfunction caused by contempt and imagined content undermines political discussion and creates terrible costs for contemned and contemner in the burdens of shame and guilt they must bear.
  •  42
    The Social and the Sociable
    Philosophical Topics 42 (1): 201-217. 2014.
    Beginning from Kant’s famous idea that “unsociable sociability” stimulates human progress and civilization, the essay investigates Kant’s categories of the “unsociable” and the “sociable,” and argues that the fundamental difference between them is that the former presuppose a social perspective that is third personal, whereas the latter is always a second-personal affair, instantiated when people relate to one another in various ways, or manifest the disposition to do so. Kant’s “unsociable” att…Read more
  •  39
    New model publishing
    The Philosophers' Magazine 14 (14): 11-12. 2001.
  •  39
    Comment on Stephen Darwall's The Second Person Standpoint
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81 (1): 246-252. 2010.
  •  37
    Reason and Value
    with E. J. Bond
    Philosophical Review 94 (2): 286. 1985.
  •  37
    Expressivist Relativism? (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (1): 183-188. 1998.