•  376
    Applied Ethics. A Defence
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 14 (4): 397-406. 2011.
    Given a reasonable coherentist view of justification in ethics, applied ethics, as here conceived of, cannot only guide us, in our practical decisions, but also provide moral understanding through explanation of our moral obligations. Furthermore, applied ethics can contribute to the growth of knowledge in ethics as such. We put moral hypotheses to crucial test in individual cases. This claim is defended against the challenges from moral intuitionism and particularism
  •  47
    Responsibility and the explanatory view of consequences
    Philosophical Studies 42 (2). 1982.
    I conclude that the explanatory view of consequences is a fruitful one.This view accounts for our common sense view that actions are, in some sense, ‘sufficient’ for their consequences. It shows in a concrete and illuminating manner that we are or may be responsible for a vast number of events no matter how ‘innocently’ our actions may be described. It allows for the fact that individuals lack responsibility for consequences of collective actions, thereby explaining a generally felt ‘double effe…Read more
  •  38
    Conservatism. A defence
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 36 (3): 329-334. 1993.
    Conservatism has an essence, or so I argue. Typical of the conservative attitude is to take what is an established fact or order to be worthy of preservation, precisely because it is well established. The question what fact is established must be answered in a context, and people of different political bent answer it differently. This is why we have left?wing as well as right?wing conservatism, sharing a common rationale. In my Conservatism for Our Time I discuss various different aspects of thi…Read more
  •  164
    Donald Davidson brought to our attention deviant causal chains as a problem for causal theories of action. Consider Davidson's own example: " A climber might want to rid himself of the weight and danger of holding another man on a rope, and he might know that by loosening his hold on the rope he could rid himself of the weight and danger. This belief and want might so unnerve him as to cause him to loosen his hold, and yet it might be the case that he never chose to loosen his hold, nor did he d…Read more
  •  2
    Medical Enhancement and the Ethos of Elite Sport
    In Julian Savulescu & Nick Bostrom (eds.), Human Enhancement, Oxford University Press. 2010.
  • Vårt ansvar för det förflutna
    Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift 6 (3): 42. 1985.
  •  28
    Transcending human limitations
    with Claudio M. Tamburrini
    Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 1 (2). 2007.
    No abstract
  •  279
    Chinese and Westerners Respond Differently to the Trolley Dilemmas
    Journal of Cognition and Culture 12 (3-4): 195-201. 2012.
    A set of moral problems known as The Trolley Dilemmas was presented to 3000 randomly selected inhabitants of the USA, Russia and China. It is shown that Chinese are significantly less prone to support utility-maximizing alternatives, as compared to the US and Russian respondents. A number of possible explanations, as well as methodological issues pertaining to the field of surveying moral judgment and moral disagreement, are discussed.
  • Död och personlig identitet
    Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift 8 (3): 25. 1987.
  •  47
    The morality of abstract entities
    Theoria 44 (1): 1-18. 1978.
  •  37
    Rational Injustice
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 36 (4): 423-439. 2006.
    Different attempts have been made to answer Reich’s question of why the majority of those who are hungry don’t steal and why the majority of those who are exploited don’t strike. The two most influential approaches have been the ideological one and the gunman theory. The gunman theory seems to have the upper hand. However, there are cases where oppression takes place in the absence of any gunman. The usual example is the democratic welfare state. We can conceive of such instances of (continued) …Read more
  •  58
    Coercive Care: The Ethics of Choice in Health and Medicine asks probing and challenging questions regarding the use of coercion in health care and social services. This book combines philosophical analysis with comparative studies of social policy and law in a large number of industrialized countries and proposes an ideal of judicial security on a global scale.
  • Replik till Per Sundström
    Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift 4. 1993.
  •  45
    Quine's Nihilism
    Ratio 15 (2): 205-219. 2002.
    Quine is an important philosopher. The point of departure of his philosophical enterprise is sound: his down to earth naturalism, his scientism and behaviourism. However, he tends to get carried away by it, when he goes to extremes – and ends up in nihilism. It is certainly true that we can never quite rule out the possibility that we have misunderstood another person. And what he or she means is a consequence mainly of two things. It is a consequence of his actual intention with the utterance a…Read more
  •  94
  • Om rationalitet
    Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift 2. 1997.
  •  61
  • Book Review-//Coercive Care: The Ethics of Choice in Health and Medicine (review)
    with Heta Aleksandra Gylling
    Bioethics 16 (1): 84-86. 2002.
  •  82
    Is Our Admiration for Sports Heroes Fascistoid?
    Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 25 (1): 23-34. 1998.
    No abstract
  •  44
    The case of biobank with the law: between a legal and scientific fiction
    with Judit Sándor, Petra Bárd, and Claudio Tamburrini
    Journal of Medical Ethics 38 (6): 347-350. 2012.
    According to estimates more than 400 biobanks currently operate across Europe. The term ‘biobank’ indicates a specific field of genetic study that has quietly developed without any significant critical reflection across European societies. Although scientists now routinely use this phrase, the wider public is still confused when the word ‘bank’ is being connected with the collection of their biological samples. There is a striking lack of knowledge of this field. In the recent Eurobarometer surv…Read more
  • En riktig hårding
    Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift 4 (2): 37. 1983.
  •  30
    Context-Dependent Preferences and the Right to Forgo Life-Saving Treatments
    Social Theory and Practice 41 (4): 716-733. 2015.
    A member of Jehovah’s Witnesses agreed to receive blood when alone, but rejected it once the elders were present. She insisted that the elders should stay, they were allowed to do so, and she bled to death. Was it all right to allow her to have the elders present when she made her final decision? Was it all right to allow her to bleed to death? It was, according to an anti-paternalist principle, which I have earlier defended on purely utilitarian grounds. The thrust of the present argument is th…Read more
  •  38
    The Expressivist Theory of Truth
    Theoria 66 (3): 256-272. 2000.
    The expressivist theory of truth (TETT) is stated and defended. According to TETT, to state such things as that it is true that snow is white is to express one's assent to the proposition that snow is white. In contexts where we refer to propositions with the aid of definite descriptions (“What Peter said”) or quantify over them (“Everything Peter says”), in order to say that they are “true”, the word “true” is essential, however. But it does not stand for any genuine property. According to TETT…Read more
  •  330
    Why We Ought to Accept the Repugnant Conclusion
    Utilitas 14 (3): 339. 2002.
    Derek Parfit has famously pointed out that ‘total’ utilitarian views, such as classical hedonistic utilitarianism, lead to the conclusion that, to each population of quite happy persons there corresponds a more extensive population with people living lives just worth living, which is better. In particular, for any possible population of at least ten billion people, all with a very high quality of life, there must be some much larger imaginable population whose existence, if other things are equa…Read more
  •  27
    Against liberty
    Journal of Value Inquiry 18 (2): 83-97. 1984.
    There are no private particular actions that should be altogether free of social interference. No absolute distinction can be made between types of actions affecting others and those affecting only the agent. Relative to a purpose in formulating an act of law, for instance, such a distinction can, however, be made. The idea of social freedom could therefore be thought to imply that even if there are no absolutely private particular actions, and even if society could interfere for any purpose to …Read more
  • Replik om terrorismen
    Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift 2 (4): 41. 1981.