• Gary Iseminger
    Sztuka I Filozofia (Art and Philosophy) 35. 2009.
  •  60
    Rationality and moral realism
    Ratio 25 (3): 345-364. 2012.
    What can a moral realist say about why we should take morality seriously and about the relation between morality and rationality? I take off from Christine Korsgaard's criticism of moral realism on this score. The aim is to achieve an understanding of the relation between moral and rational properties and of the role of practical deliberation on a realist view. I argue that the justification for being concerned with rational and moral normative properties may not be an aspect of our minds to whi…Read more
  •  20
    entry in Oxford Companion to Consciousness (ed.) Tim Bayne, Patrick Wilken and Axel Cleeremans, forthcoming.
  •  1
    The Metaphysics of Beauty
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 60 (4): 358-360. 2002.
  • Daniel O. Nathan
    Sztuka I Filozofia (Art and Philosophy) 35. 2009.
  •  167
    Negative Properties
    Noûs 45 (3): 528-556. 2011.
  •  94
    Explaining supervenience: Moral and mental
    Journal of Philosophical Research 22 (April): 509-518. 1997.
    I defend the view that supervenience relations need not be explained. My view is that some supervenience relations are brute, and explanatorily ultimate. I examine an argument of Terrence Horgan and Mark Timmons. They aim to rehabilitate John Mackie’s metaphysical queerness argument. But the explanations of supervenience that Horgan and Timmons demand are semantic explanations. I criticize their attempt to explain psychophysical supervenience in this fashion. I then turn to their ‘Twin Earth’ ar…Read more
  •  11
    The Beautiful, The Dainty And The Dumpy
    British Journal of Aesthetics 35 (4): 317-329. 1995.
  •  189
    Clouds of Illusion in the Aesthetics of Nature
    Philosophical Quarterly 63 (252): 576-596. 2013.
    I defend extreme formalism about the aesthetics of inorganic nature. I outline the general issue over aesthetic formalism as it manifests itself in the visual arts. The main issue is over whether we need to know about the history of artworks in order to appreciate them aesthetically. I then turn to nature and concede that with organic nature we need to know a thing's biological kinds if we are fully to appreciate it. However, with in organic nature I deny that we need to know the deeper nature o…Read more
  •  24
    Music, Metaphor, and Aesthetic Concepts
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 72 (1): 1-11. 2014.
    The aesthetic realist interprets many descriptions of music as metaphorical descriptions of aesthetic properties of music. I argue that aesthetic realism requires that nonaesthetic words are used to express both aesthetic and nonaesthetic concepts. But having distinguished the concepts, some plausible account must be given of their relation. A causal account of the relation between the possession of aesthetic and nonaesthetic concepts provides this, since the concepts are distinct but connected.…Read more
  •  31
    Doughnuts and Dickie
    Ratio 7 (1): 63-79. 1994.
    In this paper, I assess Dickie's institutional theory of art. I compare the earlier and later forms of the theory, and I point to various problems of detail with these accounts. I then proceed by arguing that Dickie's definition excludes Krispy Kreme doughnut boxes from possessing the status of being works of art, and it excludes those who made them from possessing the status of being artists. The intention is not to offer a counter example to Dickie's account. Rather, the complaint is that ther…Read more
  •  215
    Are there counterexamples to aesthetic theories of art?
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 60 (2). 2002.
    Do all works of art have an aesthetic purpose? It aesthetic properties are those possessed by is not particularly controversial that many works works of art or that they are those it is the funcof art have an aesthetic purpose. What will be..
  •  13
    In this volume, Zangwill develops a view of the nature of music and our experience of music that foregrounds the aesthetic properties of music. He focuses on metaphysical issues about aesthetic properties of music, psychological issues about the nature of musical experience, and philosophy of language issues about the metaphorical nature of aesthetic descriptions of music. Among the innovations of this book, Zangwill addresses the limits of literal description, generally, and in the aesthetic ca…Read more
  •  142
    Skin deep or in the eye of the beholder?: The metaphysics of aesthetic and sensory properties
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61 (3): 595-618. 2000.
    I begin this paper by describing and making attractive a physicalist aesthetic realist view of aesthetic properties. I then argue against this view on the basis of two premises. The first premise is thesis of aesthetic/sensory dependence that I have defended elsewhere. The second premise is the denial of a mind-independence thesis about sensory properties. I give an argument for that denial. Lastly, I put these two premises together and conclude that physicalist aesthetic realism is false. I art…Read more
  •  1
    Art Identity
    Dialogue 38 (2): 335-348. 1999.
    RÉSUMÉ: J’étudie la conception selon laquelle l’identité d’une œuvre d’art est déterminée par ses propriétés esthétiques; et je la compare avec la conception selon laquelle l’identité de l’œuvre d’art est déterminée par les origines de sa composition. Je soutiens que les deux théories présentent des qualités et des défauts, et que les qualités de l’une sont les défauts de l’autre. Cela nous révèle le genre de théorie dont nous avons besoin.
  •  182
    Kant on Pleasure in the Agreeable
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53 (2). 1995.
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 1995.
  •  96
    Reply to Larry Shiner on architecture
    Sztuka I Filozofia (Art and Philosophy) 35 254. 2009.
  •  17
    Unkantian Notions Of Disinterest
    British Journal of Aesthetics 31 (4): 149-152. 1991.
  •  283
    Feasible aesthetic formalism
    Noûs 33 (4): 610-629. 1999.
    Aesthetic Formalism has fallen on hard times. At best it receives unsympathetic discussion and swift rejection. At worst it is the object of abuse and derision. But I think that there is something to be said for it. In this paper, I shall try to find and secure the truth in formalism. I shall not try to defend formalism against all of the objections to it.1 Instead I shall articulate a moderate formalist view that draws on aesthetic0nonaesthetic determination and Kant’s distinction between free …Read more
  •  169
    Quasi-quasi-realism
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50 (3): 583-594. 1990.
    I. Projcctivism, Subjcctivism, and Error (i) According to Simon Blackburn, somconc who wants t0 avoid a ‘rcalistic’ account of our motal thought faces a choice} Thc choicc is bctwccn his non-rcductionist ‘projcctivism’ and rcductionist ‘subjcctivism’. Thc foymcr is thc vicw that moral judgments cxprcss attitudcs (approval, disapproval, liking or disliking, for example), which wc ‘projcct’ or ‘sprcad’ onto thc world, while thc latter is thc vicw that moral judgments arc bclicfs about attitudes. B…Read more
  •  571
    Aesthetic creation
    Oxford University Press. 2007.
    What is the purpose of art? What drives us to make it? Why do we value it? Nick Zangwill argues that the function of art is to have certain aesthetic properties in virtue of its non-aesthetic properties, and this function arises because of the artist's insight into the nature of these dependence relations and her intention to bring them about.
  •  188
    The indifference argument
    Philosophical Studies 138 (1). 2008.
    I argue against motivational internalism. First I recharacterise the issue over moral motivation. Second I describe the indifference argument against motivation internalism. Third I consider appeals to irrationality that are often made in the face of this argument, and I show that they are ineffective. Lastly, I draw the motivational externalist conclusion and reflect on the nature of the issue.
  •  241
    Daydreams and Anarchy: A Defense of Anomalous Mental Causation
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (2): 253-289. 2006.
    Must mental properties figure in psychological causal laws if they are causally efficacious? And do those psychological causal laws give the essence of mental properties? Contrary to the prevailing consensus, I argue that, on the usual conception of laws that is in play in these debates, there are in fact lawless causally efficacious properties both in and out of the philosophy of mind. I argue that this makes a great difference to the philosophical relevance of empirical psychology. 1 begin by …Read more
  •  222
    Non-cognitivism and motivation
    In Constantine Sandis (ed.), New Essays on the Explanation of Action, Palgrave-macmillan. pp. 416--24. 2009.
    In sum, the non-cognitivist account of motivation is far from unproblematic. The non-cognitivist has trouble telling us what moral attitudes are in a way that is consistent with the phenomenon of variable motivation. Given that the cognitivist has an easy explanation of variable motivation, it seems that cognitivism is preferable to non-cognitivism on the score of motivation, which is a reversal of the way the issue is usually perceived.
  •  96
    Moral modus ponens
    Ratio 5 (2): 177-193. 1992.
  •  95
    Beauty
    In Jerrold Levinson (ed.), Oxford Companion to Aesthetics, Oxford University Press. 2003.
    I shall discuss several related issues about beauty. These are: (1) The place of beauty among other aesthetic properties. (2) The general principle of aesthetic supervenience. (3) The problem of aesthetic relevance. (4) The distinction between free and dependent beauty. (5) The primacy of our appreciation of free beauty over our appreciation of dependent beauty. (6) Personal beauty as a species of beauty. (7) The metaphysics of beauty.
  •  94
    Supervenience, reduction, and infinite disjunction
    Philosophia 26 (1-2): 321-330. 1998.
    Can a certain sort of property supervene on another sort of property without reducing to it? Many philosophers find the superveniencel irreducibility combination attractive in the philosophy of mind and in moral philosophy (Davidson 1980 and Moore 1903). They think that mental properties supervene upon physical properties but do not reduce to them, or that moral properties supervene upon natural properties without reducing to them. Other philosophers have tried to show that the combination is ul…Read more
  •  1
    Against Moral Response-Dependence
    Erkenntnis 55 (2): 271-276. 2001.
  • Larry Shiner
    Sztuka I Filozofia (Art and Philosophy) 35. 2009.