•  30
    "Emotion" by William Lyons (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 45 (1): 142-149. 1984.
  •  17
    L'erotisme
    In Julien A. Deonna & Emma Tieffenbach (eds.), Petit Traité des Valeurs, Edition D’ithaque. pp. 132-139. 2018.
  •  6
    Emotional Gestalten
    Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 19 (1): 13-15. 2012.
  •  4
    The Structure of Love.Alan Soble
    Ethics 101 (4): 867-868. 1991.
  •  21
    Types and Ontology
    with Fred Sommers and John O. Nelson
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (3): 406-408. 1967.
  •  34
    Emotions, Education and Time
    Metaphilosophy 21 (4): 434-446. 1990.
  • Brian Easlea, Science and Sexual Oppression (review)
    Philosophy in Review 2 214-217. 1982.
  • Modelos conexionistas: consecuencias para la ciencia cognitiva
    Análisis Filosófico 9 (2): 183. 1989.
  •  65
    Kripke on Naming and Necessity
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 3 (3): 447-464. 1974.
    Some wag reported the following story: Scholars have recently established that the Iliad and the Odyssey were not, after all, written by Homer. They were actually written by another author, of the same name.The majority of current theories of naming and reference, including ones as divergent in other respects as those of Russell and Searle, would rule this story impossible. They would do so on roughly these grounds: the sense and reference of the name ‘Homer’ is determined, given the absence of …Read more
  •  10
    What Can’t We Do with Economics?
    Journal of Philosophical Research 22 197-209. 1997.
    Ainslie’s Picoeconomics presents an ingenious theory, based on a remarkably simple basic law about the rate of discounting the value of future prospects, which explains a vast number of psychological phenomena. Hyperbolic discount rates result in changes in the ranking of interests as they get closer in time. Thus quasi-homuncular “interests” situated at different times compete within the person. In this paper I first defend the generality of scope of Ainslie’s model, which ranges over several p…Read more
  •  168
  •  125
    The rationality of emotions
    Dialogue 18 (1): 41-63. 1979.
    Ira Brevis furor, said the Latins: anger is a brief bout of madness. There is a long tradition that views all emotions as threats to rationality. The crime passionnel belongs to that tradition: in law it is a kind of “brief-insanity defence.” We still say that “passion blinds us;” and in common parlance to be philosophical about life's trials is to be decently unemotional about them. Indeed many philosophers have espoused this view, demanding that Reason conquer Passion. Others — from Hume to th…Read more
  •  46
    Nothing seems to follow strictly from 'X believes that p'. But if we reinterpret it to mean: 'X can consistently be described as consistently believing p'--which roughly renders, I think, Hintikka's notion of "defensibility"--we can get on with the subject, freed from the inhibitions of descriptive adequacy. But defensibility is neither necessary nor sufficient for truth: it tells us little, therefore, about the concept of belief on which it is based. It cannot, in particular, specify necessary …Read more
  •  41
    Self-Deceptive Emotions
    Journal of Philosophy 75 (11). 1978.
  •  21
    Teleology and the Great Shift
    Journal of Philosophy 81 (11). 1984.
  • Stephen Toulmin, Cosmopolis: The Hidden Agenda of Modernity (review)
    Philosophy in Review 11 138-139. 1991.
  •  10
    Evolution et rationalité
    Presses universitaires de France. 2004.
    À quoi bon la pensée? Pour de nombreux chercheurs, inspirés par les théories évolutionnistes, la pensée réfléchie est utile à notre espèce. Elle lui confère des avantages importants et contribue à son succès reproductif. Pourtant ses avantages ne sont pas si évidents. La pensée ne figure ni dans les mécanismes de l'évolution qui ont façonné la vie, ni parmi les procédés dont se servent la plupart des organismes pour s'y maintenir. Dans Évolution et rationalité, Ronald de Sousa montre que, pour c…Read more
  •  279
    Restoring emotion's bad rep: the moral randomness of norms
    European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 2 (1): 29-47. 2006.
    Despite the fact that common sense taxes emotions with irrationality, philosophers have, by and large, celebrated their functionality. They are credited with motivating, steadying, shaping or harmonizing our dispositions to act, and with policing norms of social behaviour. It's time to restore emotion's bad rep. To this end, I shall argue that we should expect that some of the “norms” enforced by emotions will be unevenly distributed among the members of our species, and may be dysfunctional at …Read more
  • Comments on Barbara S. Stengel: Thinking about Thinking: Wilfred Sellars' Theory on Induction
    Philosophy of Education: Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Philosophy of Education Society 43 259-262. 1987.
  •  10
    Paradoxical emotions
    In Sarah Stroud & Christine Tappolet (eds.), Weakness of will and practical irrationality, Oxford University Press. 2003.
  •  16
    Emotions, education and time
    Metaphilosophy 21 (4): 434-446. 1990.
  •  11
    Applying Sociobiology (review)
    Biology and Philosophy 7 (2): 237. 1992.
  •  42
    Love: A Very Short Introduction
    Oxford University Press. 2015.
    Do we love someone for their virtue, their beauty, or their moral or other qualities? Are love's characteristic desires altruistic or selfish? Are there duties of love? What do the sciences tell us about love? In this Very Short Introduction, Ronald de Sousa explores the different kinds of love, from affections to romantic love.
  •  1
    Valuing Emotions (review)
    Dialogue 38 (1): 219-220. 1999.
    This book addresses both aspects of its punning title: it pleads with us to value emotions as indispensable to meaningful human life, and argues that emotions play an active role in the determination of value. The first issue is tackled with gusto. Indeed, as if to illustrate the role of the emotions in intellectual life, the tone is somewhat aggrieved, as if all but a few eccentrics in the philosophical establishment were expected to demur. Perhaps all books must pretend that their central thes…Read more
  •  167
    Teleology and the great shift
    Journal of Philosophy 81 (11): 647-653. 1984.
  • Recent Publications
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 45 (1): 151. 1984.