•  57
    Review of Daniel W. McShea and Robert N. Brandon, Biology's First Law (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2011 (1). 2011.
    McShea and Brandon propose that in the absence of constraint, biological diversity increases spontaneously. While heuristically useful, the thesis is unclear and of dubious empirical validity. The authors have no natural way to distinguish entropic decrease of diversity from the kind of increase that they are interested in. They make unsupported claims about how to explain dramatic increases of diversity and increases of functional complexity.
  •  57
    A Note on Parmenides' Denial of Past and Future
    Dialogue 25 (3): 553-. 1986.
    Does Parmenides really use the non-existence argument to deny the past?
  •  55
    Reply to Egan and Clark (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (2). 2008.
  •  48
    This collection of 25 essays by leading researchers provides an overview of the state of the field.
  •  48
    Color nominalism, pluralistic realism, and color science
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (1): 39-40. 2003.
    Byrne & Hilbert are right that it might be an objective fact that a particular tomato is unique red, but wrong that it cannot simultaneously be yellowish-red (not only objectively, but from somebody else's point of view). Sensory categorization varies among organisms, slightly among conspecifics, and sharply across taxa. There is no question of truth or falsity concerning choice of categories, only of utility and disutility. The appropriate framework for color categories is Nominalism and Plural…Read more
  •  47
    Human rationality and the unique origin constraint
    In André Ariew (ed.), Functions, Oxford University Press. pp. 341. 2002.
    This paper offers a new definition of "adaptationism". An evolutionary account is adaptationist, it is suggested, if it allows for multiple independent origins for the same function -- i.e., if it violates the "Unique Origin Constraint". While this account captures much of the position Gould and Lewontin intended to stigmatize, it leaves it open that adaptationist accounts may sometimes be appropriate. However, there are many important cases, including that of human rationality, in which it i…Read more
  •  45
    Review of Thomas Natsoulas, Consciousness and Perceptual Experience (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2014. 2014.
    A review of Thomas Natsoulas's "Consciousness and Perceptual Experience."
  •  42
    Is color perception really categorical?
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28 (4): 504-505. 2005.
    Are color categories the evolutionary product of their usefulness in communication, or is this an accidental benefit they give us? It is argued here that embodiment constraints on color categorization suggest that communication is an add-on at best. Thus, the Steels & Belpaeme (S&B) model may be important in explaining coordination, but only at the margin. Furthermore, the concentration on discrimination is questionable: coclassification is at least as important.
  •  42
    Discussion. Evolution, Wisconsin style: selection and the explanation of individual traits
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 50 (1): 143-150. 1999.
    natural selection may show why all (most, some) humans have an opposable thumb, but cannot show why any particular human has one, Karen Neander ([1995a], [1995b]) argues that this is false because natural selection is 'cumulative'. It is argued here, on grounds independent of its cumulativity, that selection can explain the characteristics of individual organisms subsequent to the event. The difference of opinion between Sober and his critics turns on an ontological dispute about how organisms a…Read more
  •  38
    What colors? Whose colors?
    Consciousness and Cognition 10 (1): 117-124. 2001.
  •  36
    Biological Realism
    Philosophica 47 (n/a). 1991.
  •  34
    How (and why) Darwinian selection restricts environmental feedback
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (3): 545-545. 2001.
    Selectionist models date back to Empedocles in Ancient Greece. The novelty of Darwinian selection is that it is able to produce adaptively valuable things without being sensitive to adaptive value. Darwin achieved this result by a restriction of environmental feedback to the replicative process. Immune system selection definitely does not respect this restriction, and it is doubtful whether operant learning does.
  •  32
    Assembling the Emotions
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36 (sup1): 185-212. 2006.
    Endogenous depression is highly correlated with low levels of serotonin in the central nervous system. Does this imply or suggest that this sort of depression just is this neurochemical deficit? Scorning such an inference, Antonio Damasio writes:If feeling happy or sad … corresponds in part to the cognitive modes under which your thoughts are operating, then the explanation also requires that the chemical acts on the circuits which generate and manipulate [such thoughts]. Which means that reduci…Read more
  •  32
    Ethics in the supply chain
    The Philosophers' Magazine 62 (62): 23-25. 2013.
  •  30
    Color vision: Content versus experience
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1): 46-47. 1992.
  •  29
    Biological Universals and the Nature of Fear
    Journal of Philosophy 95 (3): 105. 1998.
  •  22
    How Do We Know How Sensory Properties Appear? A Reply to Νenad Miščević
    Croatian Journal of Philosophy 12 (3): 509-518. 2012.
    The paper is a reply to Miščević (same volume). His objections are discussed and answered, in particular objections concerning Cartesian certainty in our knowledge of color.
  •  22
    In Mendel’s Mirror (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 102 (4): 206-216. 2005.
  •  21
    R. M. Dancy, "Sense and Contradiction" (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 16 (3): 345. 1978.
  •  19
    What Sort of Science Is Evolutionary Biology?
    Dialogue 30 (1-2): 129-. 1991.
    A review of Paul Thompson's semantic interpretation of evolutionary theory.
  •  19
    Biological Functions and Perceptual Content
    Journal of Philosophy 85 (1): 5-27. 1988.
  •  17
    Intentionality and the linguistic analogy
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 31 (1): 77-94. 2000.
  •  16
    Teleology, Error, and the Human Immune System
    with Edwin Levy
    Journal of Philosophy 81 (7): 351. 1984.
  •  14
    The Fragments of Parmenides
    with A. H. Coxon
    Philosophical Review 100 (1): 153. 1991.
  •  13
    A main point of my article, as I see it, is that we can solve Putnam's problem, as articulated in the first paragraph of section three, without recourse to the definition of “natural-kind term” as “rigid designator of a natural kind”. I had three main objections to this definition: It makes the classification of a term as a natural-kind term dependent on one's metaphysics, i.e., on the status given to natural kinds. However, Putnam's argument seems to be independent of such metaphysical consider…Read more