•  95
    Can we recreate delusions in the laboratory?
    with Rochelle Cox and Amanda Barnier
    Philosophical Psychology 25 (1). 2012.
    Clinical delusions are difficult to investigate in the laboratory because they co-occur with other symptoms and with intellectual impairment. Partly for these reasons, researchers have recently begun to use hypnosis with neurologically intact people in order to model clinical delusions. In this paper we describe striking analogies between the behavior of patients with a clinical delusion of mirrored self misidentification, and the behavior of highly hypnotizable subjects who receive a hypnotic s…Read more
  •  129
    Neurophilosophy at work • by Paul Churchland (review)
    Analysis 69 (1): 176-178. 2009.
    This is a collection of Paul Churchland's recent essays which have in common an overarching research programme aimed at identifying the scope and the importance of the contributions that neuroscience has made and will make to philosophy of mind, moral philosophy, epistemology and metaphysics. The general structure of many of the essays included in the collection is as follows: there is a long-standing problem in the philosophical literature which has escaped not only a convincing solution but al…Read more
  •  749
    The Ethics of Delusional Belief
    Erkenntnis 81 (2): 275-296. 2016.
    In this paper we address the ethics of adopting delusional beliefs and we apply consequentialist and deontological considerations to the epistemic evaluation of delusions. Delusions are characterised by their epistemic shortcomings and they are often defined as false and irrational beliefs. Despite this, when agents are overwhelmed by negative emotions due to the effects of trauma or previous adversities, or when they are subject to anxiety and stress as a result of hypersalient experience, the …Read more
  •  113
    ‘Faultless’ ignorance: Strengths and limitations of epistemic definitions of confabulation
    with Rochelle E. Cox
    Consciousness and Cognition 18 (4): 952-965. 2009.
    There is no satisfactory account for the general phenomenon of confabulation, for the following reasons: (1) confabulation occurs in a number of pathological and non-pathological conditions; (2) impairments giving rise to confabulation are likely to have different neural bases; and (3) there is no unique theory explaining the aetiology of confabulations. An epistemic approach to defining confabulation could solve all of these issues, by focusing on the surface features of the phenomenon. However…Read more
  •  689
    Animal rights, animal minds, and human mindreading
    Journal of Medical Ethics 32 (2): 84-89. 2006.
    Do non-human animals have rights? The answer to this question depends on whether animals have morally relevant mental properties. Mindreading is the human activity of ascribing mental states to other organisms. Current knowledge about the evolution and cognitive structure of mindreading indicates that human ascriptions of mental states to non-human animals are very inaccurate. The accuracy of human mindreading can be improved with the help of scientific studies of animal minds. But the scientifi…Read more
  • Double bookkeeping in delusions: Explaining the gap between saying and doing
    In Jesús H. Aguilar, Andrei A. Buckareff & Keith Frankish (eds.), New waves in philosophy of action, Palgrave-macmillan. pp. 237--256. 2011.
    In this chapter I defend the doxastic account of delusions and offer some reasons to believe that the double-bookkeeping argument against doxasticism (delusions are not beliefs because they do not drive action) should be resisted.
  •  141
    Mental illness as mental: a defence of psychological realism
    with Matthew Broome
    Humana Mente 3 (11): 25-44. 2009.
    This paper argues for psychological realism in the conception of psychiatric disorders. We review the following contemporary ways of understanding the future of psychiatry: (1) psychiatric classification cannot be successfully reduced to neurobiology, and thus psychiatric disorders should not be conceived of as biological kinds; (2) psychiatric classification can be successfully reduced to neurobiology, and thus psychiatric disorders should be conceived of as biological kinds. Position (1) can l…Read more
  •  18
    In this paper I compare different criteria for moral status, and assess Regan's notion of a "subject of a life".
  •  352
    Agency, life extension, and the meaning of life
    The Monist 93 (1): 38-56. 2010.
    Contemporary philosophers and bioethicists argue that life extension is bad for the individual. According to the agency objection to life extension, being constrained as an agent adds to the meaningfulness of human life. Life extension removes constraints, and thus it deprives life of meaning. In the paper, I concede that constrained agency contributes to the meaningfulness of human life, but reject the agency objection to life extension in its current form. Even in an extended life, decision-ma…Read more
  •  44
    Philip Gerrans the measure of madness: Philosophy of mind, cognitive neuroscience, and delusional thought
    with Rachel Gunn
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 67 (3): 919-923. 2016.
    Review of Measure of Madness
  •  708
    Rationality, diagnosis and patient autonomy
    Oxford Handbook Psychiatric Ethics. 2014.
    In this chapter, our focus is the role played by notions of rationality in the diagnosis of mental disorders, and in the practice of overriding patient autonomy in psychiatry. We describe and evaluate different hypotheses concerning the relationship between rationality and diagnosis, raising questions about what features underpin psychiatric categories. These questions reinforce widely held concerns about the use of diagnosis as a justification for overriding autonomy, which have motivated a shi…Read more
  •  167
    Intentionality without rationality
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 105 (3): 385-392. 2005.
    It is often taken for granted in standard theories of interpretation that there cannot be intentionality without rationality. According to the background argument, a system can be interpreted as having irrational beliefs only against a general background of rationality. Starting from the widespread assumption that delusions can be reasonably described as irrational beliefs, I argue here that the background argument fails to account for their intentional description
  •  140
    Irrationality
    Polity Press. 2014.
    We talk about irrationality when behaviour defies explanation or prediction, when decisions are driven by emotions or instinct rather than by reflection, when reasoning fails to conform to basic principles of logic and probability, and when beliefs lack coherence or empirical support. Depending on the context, agents exhibiting irrational behaviour may be described as foolish, ignorant, unwise or even insane. In this clear and engaging introduction to current debates on irrationality, Lisa Borto…Read more
  •  183
    Does reflection lead to wise choices?
    Philosophical Explorations 14 (3): 297-313. 2011.
    Does conscious reflection lead to good decision-making? Whereas engaging in reflection is traditionally thought to be the best way to make wise choices, recent psychological evidence undermines the role of reflection in lay and expert judgement. The literature suggests that thinking about reasons does not improve the choices people make, and that experts do not engage in reflection, but base their judgements on intuition, often shaped by extensive previous experience. Can we square the tradition…Read more
  •  66
    Large scale surveys for policy formation and research–a study in inconsistency
    with Søren Holm
    Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 28 (3): 205-220. 2007.
    In this paper we analyse the degree to which a distinction between social science and public health research and other non-research activities can account for differences between a number of large scale social surveys performed at the national and European level. The differences we will focus on are differences in how participation is elicited and how data are used for government, research and other purposes. We will argue that the research / non-research distinction does not account for the ide…Read more
  •  272
    Delusions and Other Irrational Beliefs
    Oxford University Press. 2009.
    Delusions are a common symptom of schizophrenia and dementia. Though most English dictionaries define a delusion as a false opinion or belief, there is currently a lively debate about whether delusions are really beliefs and indeed, whether they are even irrational. The book is an interdisciplinary exploration of the nature of delusions. It brings together the psychological literature on the aetiology and the behavioural manifestations of delusions, and the philosophical literature on belief asc…Read more
  •  912
    The Epistemic Benefits of Reason Giving
    Theory and Psychology 19 (5): 1-22. 2009.
    There is an apparent tension in current accounts of the relationship between reason giving and self knowledge. On the one hand, philosophers like Richard Moran (2001) claim that deliberation and justification can give rise to first-person authority over the attitudes that subjects form or defend on the basis of what they take to be their best reasons. On the other hand, the psychological evidence on the introspection effects and the literature on elusive reasons suggest that engaging in explicit…Read more
  •  759
    The Epistemic Innocence of Motivated Delusions
    Consciousness and Cognition (33): 490-499. 2015.
    Delusions are defined as irrational beliefs that compromise good functioning. However, in the empirical literature, delusions have been found to have some psychological benefits. One proposal is that some delusions defuse negative emotions and protect one from low self-esteem by allowing motivational influences on belief formation. In this paper I focus on delusions that have been construed as playing a defensive function (motivated delusions) and argue that some of their psychological benefits …Read more
  •  10
    Intentionality and the welfare of minded non-humans
    Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 29 (2): 83-96. 2010.
  •  30
    The relative importance of undesirable truths
    Medicine Healthcare and Philosophy (4): 683-690. 2012.
    The right not to know is often defended on the basis of the principle of respect for personal autonomy. If I choose not to acquire personal information that impacts on my future prospects, such a choice should be respected, because I should be able to decide whether to access information about myself and how to use it. But, according to the incoherence objection to the right not to know in the context of genetic testing, the choice not to acquire genetic information undermines the capacity for a…Read more
  •  80
    How can false or irrational beliefs be useful?
    Philosophical Explorations 20 (sup1): 1-3. 2017.
    Introduction to a special issue on False Beliefs that are Useful
  •  112
    After years of failure, in November 2007 primate embryonic stem cells were derived by somatic cellular nuclear transfer, also known as therapeutic cloning. The first embryo transfer for human reproductive cloning purposes was also attempted in 2006, albeit with negative results. These two events force us to think carefully about the possibility of human cloning which is now much closer to becoming a reality. In this paper we tackle this issue from two sides, first summarising what scientists hav…Read more
  •  701
    Disability, enhancement and the harm -benefit continuum
    In John R. Spencer & Antje Du Bois-Pedain (eds.), Freedom and Responsibility in Reproductive Choice, Hart Publishers. 2006.
    Suppose that you are soon to be a parent and you learn that there are some simple measures that you can take to make sure that your child will be healthy. In particular, suppose that by following the doctor’s advice, you can prevent your child from having a disability, you can make your child immune from a number of dangerous diseases and you can even enhance its future intelligence. All that is required for this to happen is that you (or your partner) comply with lifestyle and dietary requireme…Read more
  •  323
    Moral Responsibility and Mental Illness: A Case Study
    Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 19 (2): 179-187. 2010.
    Various authors have argued that progress in the neurocognitive and neuropsychiatric sciences might threaten the commonsense understanding of how the mind generates behavior, and, as a consequence, it might also threaten the commonsense ways of attributing moral responsibility, if not the very notion of moral responsibility. In the case of actions that result in undesirable outcomes, the commonsense conception—which is reflected in sophisticated ways in the legal conception—tells us that there a…Read more
  •  73
    Can We Interpret Irrational Behavior?
    Behavior and Philosophy 32 (2). 2004.
    According to some theories of interpretation, it is difficult to explain and predict irrational behavior in intentional terms because irrational behavior does not support the ascription of intentional states with determinate content. In this paper I challenge this claim by offering a general diagnosis of those cases in which behavior, rational or not, resists interpretation. I argue that indeterminacy of ascription and paralysis of interpretation ensue when the interpreter lacks relevant informa…Read more
  •  36
    Agency, Life Extension, and the Meaning of Life
    The Monist 93 (1): 38-56. 2010.
    According to the agency objection to life extension, being constrained as an agent adds to the meaningfulness of human life. Life extension removes constraints, and thus it deprives life of meaning. In the paper, I concede that constrained agency contributes to the mean- ingfulness of human life, but reject the agency objection to life extension in its current form. Even in an extended life, decision-making remains constrained, and many obstacles to the fulfilment of an agent’s goals are preserv…Read more
  •  143
    Précis of Delusions and Other Irrational Beliefs
    Neuroethics 5 (1): 1-4. 2012.
    Here I summarise the main arguments in Delusions and Other Irrational Beliefs [1]. The book addresses the question whether there is a rationality constraint on belief ascription and defends a doxastic account of clinical delusions.
  •  52
    If you did not care, you would not notice: recognition and estrangement in psychopathology
    with Matthew R. Broome
    Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 14 (1): 39-42. 2007.
    Paper discussing the Capgras delusions