•  31
    Context -- Overview of themes -- Reading the text -- Reception and influence.
  •  37
    Maimonides’ claim, in Guide of the Perplexed I.68, that our intellect, like God’s, becomes one with the object it knows would seem to be at odds with his injunction to his readers to set their “thought to work on the first intelligible” and to “rejoice in what [it] apprehends”. The former passage supposes that we grasp individual essences by themselves, whereas the latter supposes that such essences are known only through their first cause. Since we cannot grasp the first cause, God, we cannot, …Read more
  •  38
    The Rationality of Being
    Review of Metaphysics 68 (3): 487-520. 2015.
    This paper explores two issues: (1) how our thought about nature could reflect natural processes, and (2) how our thoughts about nature are connected with each other. It argues, first, that the standard ways philosophers try to make sense of the notion that thought is separate from nature cannot be made intelligible and, second, that the conceptual schemes used to grasp nature fall broadly into two groups each of which presupposes the other, even though the two are incompatible. Although these c…Read more
  •  26
    Klein and Cassirer
    Journal of Speculative Philosophy 29 (2): 194-217. 2015.
    ABSTRACT In Greek Mathematical Thought and the Origin of Algebra, Jacob Klein contrasts ancient Greek philosophy's direct engagement with things through arithmetic with the ancient science of numeric calculation, logistic. By chronicling the later development of logistic, by means of increasing symbolization, ultimately into algebra, he argues that logistic has come to displace arithmetic and, thereby, to submerge the ontological issues at the center of Greek thought. This article argues, first,…Read more
  •  58
  •  9
    Form and Reason: Essays in Metaphysics
    State University of New York Press. 1993.
    Many of the essays have been presented, in early or shorter versions, at various conferences. Annotation copyright by Book News, Inc., Portland, OR
  •  35
    Self-Relation in Hegel’s Science of Logic
    Philosophy Research Archives 7 89-133. 1981.
    This paper uses self-relation to reconstruct Hegel's reasoning in the Logic. In the sphere of "being," selfrelation is self-predication, and the predicate is the active, participial form of the category. Examining the first three and the last category in this sphere, I explain how Hegel argues that each category is itself engaged in the activity that it signifies. However, this self-predication adds new content to the category transforming it into a new category. Ultimately, this process leads t…Read more
  •  47
    Aristotle on the Convertibility of One and Being
    New Scholasticism 59 (2): 213-227. 1985.
  •  20
    Metaphysics Z 12 and H 6
    Ancient Philosophy 4 (2): 146-159. 1984.
  •  71
    Ackrill, Aristotle and Analytic Philosophy
    Ancient Philosophy 2 (2): 142-151. 1982.
  •  12
    The Logic of Art
    Proceedings of the Hegel Society of America 14 187-202. 2000.
  •  95
    Humor, Dialectic, and Human Nature in Plato
    Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 15 (2): 319-330. 2011.
    Drawing principally on the Symposium, this paper argues that humor in Plato’s dialogues serves two serious purposes. First, Plato uses puns and other devices to disarm the reader’s defenses and thereby allow her to consider philosophical ideas that she would otherwise dismiss. Second, insofar as human beings can only be understood through unchanging forms that we fail to attain, our lives are discontinuous and only partly intelligible. Since, though, the discontinuity between expectation and act…Read more
  •  91
    Spinoza on the Political Value of Freedom of Religion
    History of Philosophy Quarterly 21 (2): 167-182. 2004.
    The last chapter of Spinoza's Theological-Political Treatise (TTP) is a brief for freedom of religion. In our enthusiasm for Spinoza's conclusion it is easy to overlook the blatant contradiction between this thesis and the central claim of the immediately preceding chapter that "right over matters of religion is vested entirely in the sovereign." There Spinoza emphasizes the necessity that there be but one sovereign in the state and the threat that autonomous religious authorities would pose to …Read more
  •  33
    Der unbewegte Beweger des Aristoteles (review)
    Ancient Philosophy 11 (2): 439-444. 1991.
  •  77
    Aristotle’s Rethinking of Philosophy
    Proceedings of the Xxii World Congress of Philosophy 2 107-114. 2008.
    For Aristotle and other Greek thinkers, philosophy is itself a rethinking. There are other branches of knowledge, like medicine and mathematics, that each grasp some particular subject matter. Since philosophy or, as it has come to be called, metaphysics is the highest science, its job is to grasp somehow all the other sciences and all their subjects. If the science of a subject requires a type of thinking proper to the subject, then the science of that science requires a rethinking of this and …Read more
  •  45
    Primary Ousia (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 46 (3): 625-627. 1993.
    Loux sets the stage with a discussion of ousia in the Categories. There, he claims, Aristotle maintained that "basic subjects" are ontologically fundamental, and the essence of each such subject is its species. Loux thinks that Aristotle was tacitly committed to the "intersection" of these two, which he terms the "unanalyzability principle": An ousia's falling under its species is a "primitive... fact about it... not susceptible of further ontological analysis".
  •  13
  •  13
    Metaphysics Z 4-5
    Ancient Philosophy 6 (n/a): 91-122. 1986.
  •  63
    Jacob Klein on the Dispute Between Plato and Aristotle Regarding Number
    New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy 11 249-270. 2011.
    By examining Klein’s discussion of the difference between Plato and Aristotle regarding the ontology of number, this article aims to spells out the significanceof that debate both in itself and for the development of the later mathematical sciences. This is accomplished by explicating and expanding Klein’s account of the differences that exist in the understanding of number presented by these two thinkers. It is ultimately argued that Klein’s analysis can be used to show that the transition from…Read more
  •  94
    The Idealism of Hegel’s System
    The Owl of Minerva 34 (1): 19-58. 2002.
    This paper aims to show Hegel’s system to be a self-generating and conceptually closed system and, therefore, an idealism. Many readers have agreed that Hegel intends his logic to be a self-generating, closed system, but they assume that the two branches of Realphilosophie, Nature and Spirit, must involve the application of logical categories to some non-conceptual reality external to them. This paper argues that Nature emerges from logic by the reapplication of the opening logical categories to…Read more
  •  195
    Freshman Seminar Film Courses
    Teaching Philosophy 28 (4): 351-365. 2005.
    The aim of this paper is to explain how to design and teach a course that meets the special requirements of Freshman Seminar programs by using feature films to examine philosophical themes. Two such courses are discussed. By organizing each course around a theme, the teacher can use the films to illustrate and, sometimes, critique philosophical positions that she elaborates. Discussing the films, the students develop analytical and interpretive skills important for more rigorous philosophy cours…Read more
  •  9
    Colloquium 8
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 5 (1): 247-276. 1989.
  •  67
    Sachs, Joe. Aristotle's Physics: A Guided Study (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 50 (3): 687-689. 1997.
  •  43
    Aristotle on the Extension of Non-Contradiction
    History of Philosophy Quarterly 1 (4). 1984.
  •  5
    After showing how Aristotle justifies his doctrines by demonstrating how they resolve one/many problems, the author uses this justification to clarify the doctrines and what is puzzling in them.
  •  30
    Aristotle and the Philosophy of Friendship (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 57 (2): 430-432. 2003.
    Pangle’s thesis is that Aristotle’s account of friendship in Nicomachean Ethics 8 and 9 addresses multiple audiences. For his ostensible audience, statesmen and other men of action, Aristotle paints an enticing picture of friendship that is based on moral virtue and issues in acts of benevolence. However, he embeds within this analysis subtle “tensions” designed to signal to thoughtful readers the limits of moral virtue and so to provoke them to pursue a philosophical life as well as to provide …Read more