•  4
    "Rights, Goods, and Democracy" by Ramon M. Lemos (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 49 (3): 541. 1989.
  • Paternalistic Legislation
    Dissertation, The Ohio State University. 1976.
  •  62
    Killing, letting die and euthanasia
    Journal of Medical Ethics 5 (4): 200-202. 1979.
    Medical ethicists debate whether or not the moral assessment of cases of euthanasia should depend on whether the patient is 'killed' or 'allowed to die'. The usual presupposition is that a clear distinction between killing and letting die can be drawn so that this substantive question is not begged. I contend that the categorisation of cases of instances of killing rather than as instances of letting die depends in part on a prior moral assessment of the case. Hence is it trivially rather than s…Read more
  •  70
    Thirty Years of Law and Philosophy
    Law and Philosophy 30 (2): 141-142. 2011.
  •  27
    On the Rights of Non-Persons
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 10 (4). 1980.
    Do non-persons have moral rights? I will suppose this question can best be answered by inquiring whether some animals and/or environmental objects have moral rights, for if any non-persons are possessors of rights, animals and/or environmental objects are the most plausible candidates. As so interpreted, this question has received an extraordinary amount of recent attention from philosophers. Arguments have been offered and defended; rebuttals have appeared in print. Yet, so far as I am aware, n…Read more
  • Transferred Intent
    Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics and Public Policy 10 (1): 65-98. 1996.
  •  30
    Benn on privacy and respect for persons
    with Stephen D. Hudson
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 57 (4). 1979.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  53
    I examine how deferred-prosecution agreements employed against suspected corporate criminality amount to a form of social engineering that infringes the presumption. I begin with a broad understanding of the presumption itself. Then I offer a brief description of how these agreements function. Finally I address some of the normative issues that must be confronted if legal philosophers who hold retributivist views on punishment and sentencing hope to assess this device. My judgment tends to be fa…Read more
  •  267
    Four points about drug decriminalization
    Criminal Justice Ethics 22 (1): 21-29. 2003.
  •  96
    Intoxication and Culpability
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 6 (3): 363-379. 2012.
    I tackle the difficult problem of specifying how voluntary intoxication affects criminal culpability generally and recklessness in particular. I contend that the problem need not be conceptualized as an instance of actio libera in causa, namely the situation in which persons do something at t1 to culpably create the conditions of their own defense at t2. Instead, I argue that we need only consider intoxicated defendants at t2 in order to justify their punishment. In the course of defending my vi…Read more
  •  40
    Drug Proscriptions as Proxy Crimes
    Law and Philosophy 36 (4): 345-366. 2017.
    Our drug policy has been widely deemed a failure because the criminalization of drug use has not succeeded in reducing prevalence rates. I contend that the most promising basis to defend the justifiability of drug offenses is to construe them as proxy crimes: offenses designed to prevent the commission of other, more serious crimes. I make a case that many law enforcement officials use drug proscriptions for this purpose in the real world. When construed as proxy crimes, drug prohibitions are le…Read more
  •  42
    Relativistic justifications
    Law and Philosophy 19 (5). 2000.
  •  177
    Why punish the deserving?
    Noûs 26 (4): 447-464. 1992.
  •  73
    [Book review] drugs and rights (review)
    Criminal Justice Ethics 14 (1): 63-72. 1995.
    This important book was the first serious work of philosophy to address the question: Do adults have a moral right to use drugs for recreational purposes? Many critics of the 'war on drugs' denounce law enforcement as counterproductive and ineffective. Douglas Husak argues that the 'war on drugs' violates the moral rights of adults who want to use drugs for pleasure, and that criminal laws against such use are incompatible with moral rights. This is not a polemical tract but a scrupulously argue…Read more
  •  11
    Philosophical Analysis and the Limits of the Substantive Criminal Law
    Criminal Justice Ethics 18 (2): 58. 1999.
    George P. Fletcher, Basic Concepts of Criminal Law New York: Oxford University Press, 1998, xi + 223 pp.
  •  34
    The Philosophy of Criminal Law: Extending the Debates (review)
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 7 (2): 351-365. 2013.
    Larry Alexander and Peter Westen each critically examine different topics from my recent collection of essays, The Philosophy of Criminal Law. Alexander focuses on my “Rapes Without Rapists,” “Mistake of Law and Culpability,” and “Already Punished Enough.” Westen offers a more extended commentary on my “Transferred Intent.” I briefly reply to each critic in turn and try to extend the debates in new directions
  •  36
    Abetting a Crime
    Law and Philosophy 33 (1): 41-73. 2014.
    I focus on the set of problems that arise in identifying both the actus reus and (to an even greater extent) the mens rea needed by an abettor before she should be criminally liable for complicity in a crime. No consensus on these issues has emerged in positive law; commentators are enormously dissatisfied with the decisions courts have reached; and critics disagree radically about what reforms should be implemented to rectify this state of affairs. I explicitly deny that I will be able to solve…Read more
  •  37
    Obscenity and speech
    Journal of Value Inquiry 16 (1): 21-27. 1982.
  •  70
    The Criminal Law as Last Resort
    Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 24 (2): 207-235. 2004.
    In this article I examine one condition a minimalist theory of criminalization might contain: the criminal law should be used only as a last resort. I discuss how this principle should be interpreted and the reasons we have to accept it. I conclude that a theory of criminalization should probably include the (appropriately construed) last resort principle. But this conclusion will prove disappointing to those who hope to employ this principle to bring about fundamental reform in the substantive …Read more
  •  78
    I attempt to describe the several costs that criminal theory would be forced to pay by adopting the view (currently fashionable among moral philosophers) that the intentions of the agent are irrelevant to determinations of whether his actions are permissible (or criminal)
  •  16
    Editorial: Continuity Through Change (review)
    Law and Philosophy 29 (2): 123-125. 2010.
  •  38
    Rapes Without Rapists: Consent and Reasonable Mistake
    with George C. Thomas
    Philosophical Issues 11 (1): 86-117. 2001.
  •  47
    Conflicts of justifications
    Law and Philosophy 18 (1). 1999.
  •  60
    Vehicles and Crashes
    Social Theory and Practice 30 (3): 351-370. 2004.
  •  89
    Already Punished Enough
    Philosophical Topics 18 (1): 79-99. 1990.
  •  79