•  2633
    Reverence for Life as a Viable Environmental Virtue
    Environmental Ethics 25 (4): 339-358. 2003.
    There have been several recent defenses of biocentric individualism, the position that all living beings have at least some moral standing, simply insofar as they are alive. I develop a virtue-based version of biocentric individualism, focusing on a virtue of reverence for life. In so doing, I attempt to show that such a virtuebased approach allows us to avoid common objections to biocentric individualism, based on its supposed impracticability (or, on the other hand, its emptiness).
  •  858
    On Complacency
    American Philosophical Quarterly 43 (4): 343-55. 2006.
    This paper begins by drawing attention to inadequacies in common characterizations of the vice of complacency. An alternative account is presented that avoids these flaws. The distinctive nature of complacency is then clarified by contrasting it with related vices, including apathy, resignation, akrasia, excessive pride, and hypocrisy.
  •  284
    Is (merely) stalking sentient animals morally wrong?
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 17 (2). 2000.
    Such activities as tracking, watching, and photographing animals are frequently presented as morally superior alternatives to hunting, but could they themselves be morally problematic? In this paper I argue that, despite certain differences from the stalking of humans, a strong case can be made for the prima facie wrongness of stalking sentient animals. The chief harm of stalking is the fear and altered patterns of behavior which it forces upon its victims.
  •  31
    Dale Jamieson, Ethics and the Environment (review)
    Environmental Ethics 31 (3): 333-336. 2009.
    A short book review of Dale Jamieson's "Ethics and the Environment"
  •  2762
    The experience machine and mental state theories of well-being
    Journal of Value Inquiry 33 (3): 381-387. 1999.
    It is argued that Nozick's experience machine thought experiment does not pose a particular difficulty for mental state theories of well-being. While the example shows that we value many things beyond our mental states, this simply reflects the fact that we value more than our own well-being. Nor is a mental state theorist forced to make the dubious claim that we maintain these other values simply as a means to desirable mental states. Valuing more than our mental states is compatible with maint…Read more
  •  737
    Promising and supererogation
    Philosophia 32 (1-4): 389-398. 2005.
    A paradox involving promises to perform supererogatory actions is developed. Several attempts to resolve the problem, focusing in particular on changing our understanding of supererogatory actions, are explored. It is concluded that none of the proposed solutions are viable; the problem lies in promises with certain contents, not in our understanding of supererogation.
  •  1709
    Moral Realism and Arbitrariness
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 43 (1): 109-129. 2005.
    In this paper I argue (i) that choosing to abide by realist moral norms would be as arbitrary as choosing to abide by the mere preferences of a God (a difficulty akin to the Euthyphro dilemma raised for divine command theorists); in both cases we would lack reason to prefer these standards to alternative codes of conduct. I further develop this general line of thought by arguing in particular (ii) that we would lack any noncircular justification to concern ourselves with any such realist normati…Read more
  •  179
    Harry G. Frankfurt, The Reasons of Love (review)
    Philosophy in Review 24 (5): 322-324. 2004.
  •  284
    Ronald Sandler and Philip Cafaro, Environmental Virtue Ethics (review)
    Environmental Ethics 28 (4): 429-32. 2006.
    A short review of "Environmental Virtue Ethics" (2005), a collection edited by Ronald Sandler and Philip Cafaro.
  •  1563
    Autonomy, agency, and the value of enduring beliefs
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 40 (1). 2010.
    My central thesis is that philosophers considering questions of epistemic value ought to devote greater attention to the enduring nature of beliefs. I begin by arguing that a commonly drawn analogy between beliefs and actions is flawed in important respects, and that a better, more fruitful analogue for belief would be desire, or a similarly enduring state of an agent. With this in hand, I argue that treating beliefs as enduring, constitutive states of agents allows us to capture the importance …Read more
  •  29
    Alan Thomas, Value and Context: The Nature of Moral and Political Knowledge (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2007 (9). 2007.
    This is, surprisingly enough, a review of Alan Thomas' "Value and Context: The Nature of Moral and Political Knowledge". A very nice book. More details in the review itself.
  •  1205
    Other–regarding epistemic virtues
    Ratio 15 (3). 2002.
    Epistemologists often assume that an agent’s epistemic goal is simply to acquire as much knowledge as possible for herself. Drawing on an analogy with ethics and other practices, I argue that being situated in an epistemic community introduces a range of epistemic virtues (and goals) which fall outside of those typically recognized by both individualistic and social epistemologists. Candidate virtues include such traits as honesty, integrity (including an unwillingness to misuse one’s status as …Read more
  •  184
    John Cottingham, On the Meaning of Life (review)
    Philosophy in Review 24 (1): 22-24. 2004.