Boston University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1985
Victoria, British Columbia, Canada
  •  17
    Defining art responsibly
    British Journal of Aesthetics 37 (1): 57-65. 1997.
  •  144
    The cognitive value of music
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 57 (1): 41-54. 1999.
  •  20
    Semantic Challenges to Realism (review)
    Dialogue 41 (2): 405-406. 2002.
    Semantic realism is the view that sentences can be true even if speakers cannot know that they are. Anti-realists believe that sentences cannot be true unless speakers can know that they are. The difference between the two positions can be characterized as a dispute about truth conditions. Realists believe that they are objective, that is, they can obtain even though speakers cannot know that they do. Anti-realists believe that truth conditions are always recognizable. Two major lines of argumen…Read more
  •  1
    Art and Knowledge
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 63 (2): 198-200. 2005.
  •  15
    Reality and Reason (review)
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (2): 491-500. 1987.
  •  16
  •  81
    Global anti-realism
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 47 (4): 641-647. 1987.
  •  188
    The slingshot argument and the correspondence theory of truth
    Acta Analytica 17 (2): 121-132. 2002.
    The correspondence theory of truth holds that each true sentence corresponds to a discrete fact. Donald Davidson and others have argued (using an argument that has come to be known as the slingshot) that this theory is mistaken, since all true sentences correspond to the same “Great Fact.” The argument is designed to show that by substituting logically equivalent sentences and coreferring terms for each other in the context of sentences of the form ‘P corresponds to the fact that P’ every true s…Read more
  •  12
    Charles Batteux: The Fine Arts Reduced to a Single Principle (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2015.
    The Fine Arts Reduced to a Single Principle by Charles Batteux was arguably the most influential work on aesthetics published in the 18th century. James O. Young presents the first complete English translation of the work, with full annotations and a comprehensive introduction, which illuminate Batteux's continuing philosophical interest.
  •  235
    Truth, correspondence and deflationism
    Frontiers of Philosophy in China 4 (4): 563-575. 2009.
    The central claim of this essay is that many deflationary theories of truth are variants of the correspondence theory of truth. Essential to the correspondence theory of truth is the proposal that objective features of the world are the truthmakers of statements. Many advocates of deflationary theories (including F. P. Ramsay, P. F. Strawson and Paul Horwich) remain committed to this proposal. Although T-sentences (statements of the form “ s is true iff p ”) are presented by advocates of deflati…Read more
  •  2
    Authenticity in performance
    In Berys Nigel Gaut & Dominic Lopes (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics, Routledge. 2000.
  •  74
    Artworks and artworlds
    British Journal of Aesthetics 35 (4): 330-337. 1995.
  • Michael Dummett, Thought and Reality
    Philosophy in Review 27 (5): 334. 2007.
  •  37
    Inquiry in the Arts and Sciences
    Philosophy 71 (276): 255-273. 1996.
    In his 1836 lectures to the Royal Institute, the great landscape painter John Constable stated that ‘Painting is a science, and should be pursued as an inquiry into the laws of nature.’ Landscape, he went on to say, should ‘be considered a branch of natural philosophy, of which pictures are but the experiments.’1Constable makes two claims in this striking passage. The first is that painting is a form of inquiry. This is, by itself, a bold claim, but Constable goes on to state that painters and s…Read more
  •  97
    Destroying works of art
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 47 (4): 367-373. 1989.
  •  64
    The ‘great divide’ in music
    British Journal of Aesthetics 45 (2): 175-184. 2005.
    Several prominent philosophers of music, including Lydia Goehr and Peter Kivy, maintain that the experience of music changed drastically in about 1800. According to the great divide hypothesis, prior to 1800 audiences often scarcely attended to music. At other times, music was appreciated as part of social, civic, or religious ceremonies. After the great divide, audiences began to appreciate music as an exclusive object of aesthetic experience. The great divide hypothesis is false. The musicolog…Read more
  •  63
    Between rock and a Harp place
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53 (1): 78-81. 1995.
  •  102
    Art and the educated audience
    Journal of Aesthetic Education 44 (3): 29-42. 2010.
    When writing about art, aestheticians tend to focus on the work of art and on the artist who produces it. When they refer to audiences, they typically speak only of the effect that the artwork has on its audience. Aestheticians pay little, if any, attention to the important active role that an audience plays in the workings of a healthy art world. My goal in this essay is to do something to end the neglect of the audience. I will focus on the role of the informed or, as I will call it, educated …Read more
  •  46
    Relativism and the Evaluation of Art
    The Journal of Aesthetic Education 31 (1): 9. 1997.
  •  20
    Relativism and anti-realism
    Ratio 9 (1): 68-77. 1996.
    I characterise a relativist account of truth as one according to which the truth value of a sentence can vary without its meaning changing. Relativism is to be contrasted with absolutism, which states that the truth values of sentences cannot change, so long as their meanings remain constant. I argue that absolutism follows from the realist account of meaning and truth conditions. According to realism, the meaning of a sentence consists in objective truth conditions and sentences are true if and…Read more
  •  38
    Kivy on Musical Genius
    British Journal of Aesthetics 51 (1): 1-12. 2011.
    Peter Kivy argues that Handel was the first composer to be regarded as a genius and that only in the eighteenth century was the philosophical apparatus in place that would enable any composer to be conceived of as a musical genius. According to Kivy, a Longinian conception of genius transformed Handel into a genius. A Platonic conception of genius was used to classify Mozart as a genius. Then Kant adopted a Longinian conception of genius and this shaped the perception of Beethoven. Kivy is wrong…Read more
  •  4
    Global Anti-Realism (review)
    Dialogue 40 (4): 814-815. 2001.
    Full disclosure: I am the author of a book with a title only typographically different from that of the one under review. The present book is avowedly hostile to global anti-realism while mine is a sustained defence of the position. My route to global anti-realism is discounted by page 4 of Cortens’s book. If my remarks sometimes have a critical tenor, no one should be surprised. Still, I found much to admire in this book. It contributes significantly to our understanding of global anti-realism.
  •  18
    The Semantics of Aesthetic Judgements (edited book)
    Oxford University Press UK. 2017.
    Are aesthetic judgements simply expressions of personal preference? If two people disagree about the beauty of a painting are both judgements valid or can someone be mistaken about the aesthetic value of an artwork? This volume brings together some of the leading philosophers of art and language to debate the status of aesthetic judgements.
  •  4
    Critical Notice
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (2): 491-500. 1987.
  •  143
    The concept of authentic performance
    British Journal of Aesthetics 28 (3): 228-238. 1988.
  •  101
    Art, knowledge, and exemplification
    British Journal of Aesthetics 39 (2): 126-137. 1999.