•  56
    The Analogy Argument for a Limited Acccount of Omniscience
    International Philosophical Quarterly 29 (2): 129-138. 1989.
    IN COMPARISON with other doctrines Cthe doctrine of omnipotence, for example Cthe proper formulation of the doctrine of omniscience has not seemed especially problematic. Once we accept the contemporary wisdom that knowledge is knowledge of truths, the formulation of the traditional doctrine seems straightforward: to be omniscient is just to know all truths. What has seemed problematic, rather, is whether the doctrine is itself true. In particular, many have wondered whether anyone can know the …Read more
  •  55
    Intellectual Humility: Lessons from the Preface Paradox
    Res Philosophica 93 (3): 1-532. 2016.
    One response to the preface paradox—the paradox that arises when each claim in a book is justified for the author and yet in the preface the author avers that errors remain—counsels against the preface belief. It is this line of thought that poses a problem for any view that places a high value on intellectual humility. If we become suspicious of preface beliefs, it will be a challenge to explain how expressions of fallibility and intellectual humility are appropriate, whether voiced verbally or…Read more
  •  54
    ``Coherentism: Misconstrual and Misapprehension"
    Southwest Philosophy Review 11 (1): 159-169. 1995.
    Some critics of coherentism have depicted it so that it founders on the distinction between warrant for the content of a belief and warrant for the believing itself. This distinction has to do with the basing relation: one might have warrant for the content of what one believes without basing one's belief properly, without holding the belief because of what warrants it. When the first kind of warrant obtains, I will say that a belief is propositionally warranted.
  •  54
  •  53
    Is there an 'us' in 'justification'?
    Synthese 62 (1). 1985.
    A critical question for epistemologists is whether there are any inter-subjective requirements for having a justified belief C whether there is an >us= in >justification=. One recent epistemologist that has addressed this issue is Keith Lehrer. In Knowledge, Lehrer presents a..
  •  52
    Further Thoughts on Agent Reliabilism
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66 (2): 466-480. 2003.
    Though I find the project significant and unprecedented in this way, I am not convinced that it is entirely successful, and I will try to explain here the grounds of my concern. We can begin with Greco’s list of requirements for an adequate theory of knowledge, and the relationship he sees between simple reliabilism and his own theory, agent reliabilism.
  •  51
    Theories of Providence and Creation
    Res Philosophica 90 (1): 49-67. 2013.
    Einstein was notoriously confident that God doesn’t play dice with the universe. Perhaps it is a confidence born of a deeper modal presumption: that Godcouldn’t play dice with the universe. If so, such confidence almost certainly disappoints. Even if God doesn’t play dice with the universe, he might. Thus arises the issue here addressed: what implications does this datum have for a proper understanding of divine providence? My interest is in theories that aim to present complete theories of prov…Read more
  •  51
    Jonathan L. Kvanvig presents a new account of rationality, Perspectivalism, which both avoids elevating rationality so that only the most reflective of us are capable of rational beliefs, and avoids reducing it to the level of beasts. He defends optionality about what it is reasonable to think, and provides a framework for rational disagreement.
  •  50
  •  48
    Comment: Jonathan L. Kvanvig
    Southwest Philosophy Review 1 182-186. 1984.
  •  48
    “He who lapse last lapse best”: Plantinga on leibniz’s lapse
    Southwest Philosophy Review 10 (1): 137-146. 1994.
  •  45
    The Intellectual Virtues and the Life of the Mind (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (4): 973-976. 1994.
  •  45
    Divine Transcendence
    Religious Studies 20 (3). 1984.
    representations, for the unconditioned transcendent surpasses every possible conception of a being, including even the conception of a Supreme Being... It is the religious function of atheism ever to remind us that the religious act has to do with the unconditioned transcendent, and that the representations of the Unconditioned are not objects concerning whose existence.., a discussion would be possible. The word >God= involves a double meaning: it connotes the unconditioned transcendent, the ul…Read more
  •  44
    On Denying a Presupposition of Sellars' Problem:A Defense of Propositionalism
    Veritas – Revista de Filosofia da Pucrs 50 (4): 173-190. 2005.
    There is a great divide between two approaches to epistemology over the past thirty to forty years. Some label the divide that between internalists and externalists, and that characterization may be accurate on some account of the distinction. I will pursue the divide from a different direction, in part because the literature on the distinction between internalism and externalism has become a mess, and I don’t want to clean up the mess here
  •  41
    Hasker on fatalism
    Philosophical Studies 65 (1-2). 1992.
  •  41
    ``Nozickian Epistemology and the Question of Closure"
    Croatian Journal of Philosophy 3 (3): 351-364. 2004.
    Nozick’s contribution to the epistemology of the last half of the twentieth century includes addressing the question of whether knowledge is closed under known implication. I argue that the question of closure provides a serious obstacle to Nozickian approaches to epistemology
  •  40
    Sosa's virtue epistemology
    Critica 42 (125): 47-62. 2010.
    Ernest Sosa's latest epistemology remains a version of virtue epistemology, and I argue here that it faces two central problems, pressing a point I have made elsewhere, that virtue epistemology does not present a complete answer to the problem of the value of knowledge. I will press this point regarding the nature of knowledge through variations on two standard Gettier examples here. The first is the Fake Barn case and the second is the Tom Grabit case. I will argue that Sosa's latest virtue epi…Read more
  •  38
    In defending his rejection of Maverick Molinism (Faith and Philosophy 20.1, (January 2003), pp. 91-100) from my criticisms (Faith and Philosophy 19 (2002), pp. 348-357), Tom Flint attributes three central claims to my argument, and disagrees with two of them. He also notes my request for a defense of the Law of Conditional Excluded Middle, which his argument employs. He portrays that discussion as taking “potshots” at his argument, in part because I denied that concerns about the Law are compell…Read more
  •  35
    The knowability paradox derives from a proof by Frederic Fitch in 1963. The proof purportedly shows that if all truths are knowable, it follows that all truths are known. Antirealists, wed as they are to the idea that truth is epistemic, feel threatened by the proof. For what better way to express the epistemic character of truth than to insist that all truths are knowable? Yet, if that insistence logically compels similar assent to some omniscience claim, antirealism is in jeopardy. Response to…Read more
  •  35
    Truth and superassertibility
    Philosophical Studies 93 (1): 1-19. 1999.
  •  35
    How to Be a Reliabilist
    American Philosophical Quarterly 23 (2). 1986.
    In recent years, epistemologists have become increasingly impressed with reliabilist theories of justification. 1 Reliabilism is often formulated as the claim that a belief is justified 2 just in case it is a reliable belief; however, this formulation can be somewhat misleading. There is a sense in which a set of beliefs can be reliable, just as a certain history or testimony can be reliable: what one means is that a certain set of propositions is highly accurate, has mostly true members, or is …Read more
  •  32
    Perceiving God (review)
    Faith and Philosophy 11 (2): 311-321. 1994.
  •  29
    Virtue Epistemology
    In Sven Bernecker & Duncan Pritchard (eds.), Routledge Companion to Epistemology, Routledge. pp. 199--207. 2010.
  •  28
    ``Precìs of T he Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding "
    In Pritchard, Haddock & MIllar (eds.), Epistemic Value, Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 309--313. 2009.
    Reflection on the issues surrounding the value of knowledge and other cognitive states of interest to epistemologists can be traced to the conversation between Socrates and Meno in Plato’s dialogue named after the latter. The context of discussion concerns the hiring of a guide to get one to Larissa, and the proposal on the table is that one would want a guide who knows the way. Socrates sees a problem, however, for it is not clear why a guide with merely true opinion will not be just as good.
  •  27
    Book reviews (review)
    with David Wisdo and Donald Wayne Viney
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 36 (1): 57-63. 1994.
  •  26
    In Defense of Coherentism
    Journal of Philosophical Research 22 299-306. 1997.
    Alvin Plantinga and John Pollock both think that coherentism is a mistaken theory of justification, and they do so for different reasons. In spite of these differences, there are remarkable connections between their criticisms. Part of my goal here is to show what these connections are. I will show that Plantinga’s construal of coherentism presupposes Pollock’s arguments against that view, and I will argue that coherentists need not breathe their last in response to the contentions of either. Co…Read more
  •  25
    Ontology, Identity, and Modality (review)
    Faith and Philosophy 22 (1): 105-106. 2005.
  •  24
    Credulism
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 16 (2). 1984.
    Some recent philosophers of religion have addressed the question of how, and whether it is possible, that the religious experiences some persons have had can give reasons for believing that God exists. Swinburne, for example, claims that what he calls the principle of credulity implies that the religious experiences of those that have them do provide evidence for others that God exists. He formulates the principle as follows: 1 (1) if it seems (epistemically) to a subject that x is present, then…Read more