•  107
    This book brings cutting edge neuroscience and psychology into dialogue with philosophical reflection to illuminate the loss of control experienced by addicts, and thereby cast light on ordinary agency and the way in which it sometimes goes wrong
  •  103
    Echoes of covid misinformation
    Philosophical Psychology 36 (5): 931-948. 2021.
    Public support for responses to the coronavirus pandemic has sharply diverged on partisan lines in many countries, with conservatives tending to oppose lockdowns, social distancing, mask mandates and vaccines, and liberals far more supportive. This polarization may arise from the way in which the attitudes of each side is echoed back to them, especially on social media. In this paper, I argue that echo chambers are not to blame for this polarization, even if they are causally responsible for it.…Read more
  •  96
    Cases in which we find ourselves irrationally worried about whether we have done something we habitually do are familiar to most people, but they have received surprisingly little attention in the philosophical literature. In this paper, I argue that available accounts designed to explain superficially similar mismatches between agents’ behavior and their beliefs fail to explain these cases. In the kinds of cases which have served as paradigms for extant accounts, contents are poised to drive be…Read more
  •  96
    Are We Agents at All? Helen Steward's Agency Incompatibilism
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 56 (4): 386-399. 2013.
    ABSTRACT In A Metaphysics for Freedom and related papers, Helen Steward advances a new argument for incompatibilism. Though she concedes that the luck objection is persuasive with regard to existing versions of libertarianism, she claims that agency itself is incompatible with determinism: we are only agents at all if we are able to settle matters concerning our movements, where settling something requires that prior to our settling it lacked sufficient conditions. She argues that genuine agents…Read more
  •  95
    In Trust We Trust: Epistemic Vigilance and Responsibility
    Social Epistemology 36 (3): 283-298. 2022.
    Much of what we know we know through testimony, and knowing on the basis of testimony requires some degree of trust in speakers. Trust is therefore very valuable. But in trusting, we expose ourselves to risks of harm and betrayal. It is therefore important to trust well. In this paper, I discuss two recent cases of the betrayal of trust in (broadly) academic contexts: one involving hoax submissions to journals, the other faking an identity on social media. I consider whether these betrayals sugg…Read more
  •  95
    Restrictivism is a Covert compatibilism
    In Nick Trakakis & Daniel Cohen (eds.), Essays on free will and moral responsibility, Cambridge Scholars Press. 2008.
    _Libertarian restrictivists hold that agents are rarely directly free. However, they seek to reconcile their views_ _with common intuitions by arguing that moral responsibility, or indirect freedom (depending on the version of_ _restrictivism) is much more common than direct freedom. I argue that restrictivists must give up either the_ _claim that agents are rarely free, or the claim that indirect freedom or responsibility is much more common_ _than direct freedom. Focusing on Kane’s version of …Read more
  •  91
    What in the World Is Collective Responsibility?
    Dialectica 72 (2): 191-217. 2018.
  •  90
    Ecological Engineering: Reshaping Our Environments to Achieve Our Goals
    Philosophy and Technology 25 (4): 589-604. 2012.
    Human beings are subject to a range of cognitive and affective limitations which interfere with our ability to pursue our individual and social goals. I argue that shaping our environment to avoid triggering these limitations or to constrain the harms they cause is likely to be more effective than genetic or pharmaceutical modifications of our capacities because our limitations are often the flip side of beneficial dispositions and because available enhancements seem to impose significant costs.…Read more
  •  89
    Philosophy’s other climate problem☆
    Journal of Social Philosophy 52 (4): 536-553. 2021.
    Journal of Social Philosophy, Volume 52, Issue 4, Page 536-553, Winter 2021.
  •  88
    You meta believe it
    European Journal of Philosophy 26 (2): 814-826. 2018.
    Because of the privileged place of beliefs in explaining behaviour, mismatch cases—in which agents sincerely claim to believe that p, but act in a way that is inconsistent with that belief—have attracted a great deal of attention. In this paper, I argue that some of these cases, at least, are at least partially explained by agents believing that they believe that p, while failing to believe that p. Agents in these cases do not believe that ~p; rather, they have an indistinct first‐order, beliefy…Read more
  •  84
    Zimmerman’s The Immorality of Punishment: A Critical Essay (review)
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 9 (1): 103-112. 2015.
    In “The Immorality of Punishment”, Michael Zimmerman attempts to show that punishment is morally unjustified and therefore wrong. In this response, I focus on two main questions. First, I examine whether Zimmerman’s empirical claims—concerning our inability to identify wrongdoers who satisfy conditions on blameworthiness and who might be reformed through punishment, and the comparative efficacy of punitive and non-punitive responses to crime—stand up to scrutiny. Second, I argue that his crucial…Read more
  •  83
    What (if Anything) Is Wrong with Bestiality?
    Journal of Social Philosophy 34 (3): 444-456. 2003.
  •  82
    The wisdom of the pack
    Philosophical Explorations 9 (1). 2006.
    This short article is a reply to Fine's criticisms of Haidt's social intuitionist model of moral judgement. After situating Haidt in the landscape of meta-ethical views, I examine Fine's argument, against Haidt, that the processes which give rise to moral judgements are amenable to rational control: first-order moral judgements, which are automatic, can nevertheless deliberately be brought to reflect higher-order judgements. However, Haidt's claims about the arationality of moral judgements seem…Read more
  •  80
    Deafness, culture, and choice
    Journal of Medical Ethics 28 (5): 284-285. 2002.
    We should react to deaf parents who choose to have a deaf child with compassion not condemnationThere has been a great deal of discussion during the past few years of the potential biotechnology offers to us to choose to have only perfect babies, and of the implications that might have, for instance for the disabled. What few people foresaw is that these same technologies could be deliberately used to ensure that children would be born with disabilities. That this is a real possibility, and not …Read more
  •  76
    Taking Responsibility for Responsibility
    Public Health Ethics 12 (2): 103-113. 2019.
    Governments, physicians, media and academics have all called for individuals to bear responsibility for their own health. In this article, I argue that requiring those with adverse health outcomes to bear responsibility for these outcomes is a bad basis for policy. The available evidence strongly suggests that the capacities for responsible choice, and the circumstances in which these capacities are exercised, are distributed alongside the kinds of goods we usually talk about in discussing distr…Read more
  •  76
    Routledge Companion to Free Will. (edited book)
    Routledge. 2017.
    Questions concerning free will are intertwined with issues in almost every area of philosophy, from metaphysics to philosophy of mind to moral philosophy, and are also informed by work in different areas of science. Free will is also a perennial concern of serious thinkers in theology and in non-western traditions. Because free will can be approached from so many different perspectives and has implications for so many debates, a comprehensive survey needs to encompass an enormous range of approa…Read more
  •  73
    Morality on the brain (review)
    The Philosophers' Magazine 54 (54): 108-109. 2011.
  •  67
    Beta adrenergic blockade reduces utilitarian judgement
    with Sylvia Terbeck, Guy Kahane, Sarah McTavish, Julian Savulescu, Miles Hewstone, and Philip Cowen
    Biological Psychology 92 (2): 323-328. 2013.
    Noradrenergic pathways are involved in mediating the central and peripheral effects of physiological arousal. The aim of the present study was to investigate the role of noradrenergic transmission in moral decision-making. We studied the effects in healthy volunteers of propranolol (a noradrenergic beta-adrenoceptor antagonist) on moral judgement in a set of moral dilemmas pitting utilitarian outcomes (e.g., saving five lives) against highly aversive harmful actions (e.g., killing an innocent pe…Read more
  •  66
    When Is Company Unwelcome?
    Episteme 20 (1): 101-106. 2023.
    In a recent paper in this journal, Joshua Blanchard has identified a novel problem: the problem of unwelcome epistemic company. We find ourselves in unwelcome epistemic company when we hold a belief that is also held mainly or most prominently by those we regard as morally or epistemically bad. Blanchard argues that some, but not all, unwelcome epistemic company provides higher-order evidence against our belief. But he doesn't provide a test for when company is unwelcome or a diagnosis of why it…Read more
  •  65
    Introduction: Appiah’s Experiments in Ethics (review)
    Neuroethics 3 (3): 197-200. 2010.
  •  65
    Bad beliefs – a precis
    Philosophical Psychology 36 (4): 772-777. 2023.
    This brief paper sketches the main theses of my recent book Bad Beliefs. The book defends the view that human cognition is more evidence responsive than most psychologists and naturalistic philosophers think. In particular, we are responsive to the abundant higher-order evidence that we encounter in experiments and in everyday life.
  •  64
    The regulation of cognitive enhancement devices : extending the medical model
    with Hannah Maslen, Thomas Douglas, Roi Cohen Kadosh, and Julian Savulescu
    Journal of Law and the Biosciences 1 (1): 68-93. 2014.
    This article presents a model for regulating cognitive enhancement devices. Recently, it has become very easy for individuals to purchase devices which directly modulate brain function. For example, transcranial direct current stimulators are increasingly being produced and marketed online as devices for cognitive enhancement. Despite posing risks in a similar way to medical devices, devices that do not make any therapeutic claims do not have to meet anything more than basic product safety stand…Read more
  •  64
    The Surprising Truth About Disagreement
    Acta Analytica 36 (2): 137-157. 2020.
    Conciliationism—the thesis that when epistemic peers discover that they disagree about a proposition, both should reduce their confidence—faces a major objection: it seems to require us to significantly reduce our confidence in our central moral and political commitments. In this paper, I develop a typology of disagreement cases and a diagnosis of the source and force of the pressure to conciliate. Building on Vavova’s work, I argue that ordinary and extreme disagreements are surprising, and for…Read more
  •  63
    Do-it-yourself brain stimulation: a regulatory model
    with Hannah Maslen, Tom Douglas, Roi Cohen Kadosh, and Julian Savulescu
    Journal of Medical Ethics 41 (5): 413-414. 2015.
  •  59
    Conspiracy Theories (review)
    Inquiry: Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines 24 (1-2): 47-48. 2004.
  •  59
    Putting the Luck Back Into Moral Luck
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 43 (1): 59-74. 2019.
    Midwest Studies In Philosophy, EarlyView.