•  111
    The Nature of Normativity: Reply to Holton, Railton, and Lenman
    Philosophical Studies 151 (3): 479-491. 2010.
    In this article, I reply to the comments that Richard Holton, Peter Railton, and James Lenman have made on my 2007 book "The Nature of Normativity".
  •  109
    Non-cognitivism, truth and logic
    Philosophical Studies 86 (1): 73-91. 1997.
    This paper provides a new argument for a position of Crispin Wright's: given that ethical statements can be embedded within all sorts of sentential operators and are subject to definite standards of warrantedness, they must have truth conditions. Allan Gibbard's normative logic' is the only noncognitivist logic that stands a chance of avoiding Geach's Fregean objection. But what, according to Gibbard, is the point of avoiding inconsistency in one's ethical statements? He must say that it is to e…Read more
  •  104
    Moral Disagreement and Inexcusable Irrationality
    American Philosophical Quarterly 56 (1): 97. 2019.
    This essay explores the following position: Ultimate moral principles are a priori truths; hence, it is irrational to assign a non-zero credence to any proposition that is incompatible with these ultimate moral principles ; and this sort of irrationality, if it could have been avoided, is in a sense inexcusable. So—at least if moral relativism is false—in any disagreement about ultimate moral principles, at least one party to the disagreement is inexcusably irrational. This position may seem ext…Read more
  •  94
    Christopher Peacocke's The Realm of Reason (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74 (3): 776-791. 2007.
    In this book, Christopher Peacocke proposes a general theory about what it is for a thinker to be entitled to form a given belief. This theory is distinctively rationalist: that is, it gives a large role to the a priori, while insisting that the propositions or contents that can be known a priori are not in any way “true in virtue of meaning” (and without in any other way denigrating these propositions as “trivial”, or as propositions that “tell us nothing about the world”, or the like). Peacock…Read more
  •  92
    Railton on normativity (review)
    Philosophical Studies 126 (3): 463-479. 2005.
    This is a critical discussion of Part III of Peter Railton's recent book Facts, Values, and Norms: Essays Toward a Morality of Consequence (Cambridge University Press, 2003).
  •  87
    A probabilistic epistemology of perceptual belief
    Philosophical Issues 28 (1): 1-25. 2018.
    There are three well-known models of how to account for perceptual belief within a probabilistic framework: (a) a Cartesian model; (b) a model advocated by Timothy Williamson; and (c) a model advocated by Richard Jeffrey. Each of these models faces a problem—in effect, the problem of accounting for the defeasibility of perceptual justification and perceptual knowledge. It is argued here that the best way of responding to this the best way of responding to this problem effectively vindicates the …Read more
  •  85
    The Price of Non‐Reductive Physicalism
    Noûs 34 (3): 400-421. 2000.
    Nonreductive physicalism faces a serious objection: physicalism entails the existence of an enormous number of modal facts--specifically, facts about exactly which physical properties necessitate each mental property; and, it seems, if mental properties are irreducible, these modal facts cannot all be satisfactorily explained. The only answer to this objection is to claim that the explanations of these modal facts are themselves contingent. This claim requires rejecting "S5" as the appropriate l…Read more
  •  84
    The Value of Rationality
    Oxford University Press. 2017.
    Ralph Wedgwood gives a general account of what it is for states of mind and processes of thought to count as rational. Whether you are thinking rationally depends purely on what is going on in your mind, but rational thinking is a means to the goal of getting things right in your thinking, by believing the truth or making good choices.
  •  76
    The diversity of topics discussed in this book reflects the breadth of Judith Jarvis Thomson's philosophical work. Throughout her long career at MIT, Thomson's straightforward approach and emphasis on problem-solving have shaped philosophy in significant ways. Some of the book's contributions discuss specific moral and political issues such as abortion, self-defense, the rights and obligations of prospective fathers, and political campaign finance. Other contributions concern the foundations of …Read more
  •  61
    Critical Notice of "The Realm of Reason" by Christopher Peacocke (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74 (3): 776-791. 2007.
    This is a critical notice of Christopher Peacocke's book, "The Realm of Reason" (Oxford University Press, 2004)
  •  60
    Practical and Theoretical Rationality
    In Markus Knauff & Wolfgang Spohn (eds.), The Handbook of Rationality, Mit Press. pp. 137-145. 2021.
    Philosophers have long distinguished between practical and theoretical rationality. The first section of this chapter begins by discussing the ways in which this distinction was drawn by Aristotle and Kant; then it sketches what seems to be the general consensus today about how, at least roughly, the distinction should be drawn. The rest of this chapter explores what practical and theoretical rationality have in common: in the second section, several parallels between practical and theoretical r…Read more
  •  57
    This is a review of Clare Chambers's book, Against Marriage: An Egalitarian Defense of the Marriage-Free State.
  •  55
    Fifteen Sermons and Other Writings on Ethics by Joseph Butler (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 56 (3): 563-564. 2018.
    As a young Anglican clergyman, Joseph Butler published the first edition of his Fifteen Sermons Preached at the Rolls Chapel in 1721; a revised edition appeared in 1729. Almost immediately, it was widely understood that these sermons present a strikingly subtle and careful form of a relatively traditional conception of ethics, in contrast to the more radical views of other philosophers such as Thomas Hobbes. Only a few years later, David Hume was much concerned to assimilate Butler's insights, w…Read more
  •  53
    The fundamental principle of practical reasoning
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 6 (2). 1998.
    The fundamental principle of practical reasoning (if there is such a thing) must be a rule which we ought to follow in all our practical reasoning, and which cannot lead to irrational decisions. It must be a rule that it is possible for us to follow directly - that is, without having to follow any other rule of practical reasoning in order to do so. And it must be a basic principle, in the sense that the explanation of why we rationally ought to follow this rule lies purely in the structure of o…Read more
  •  49
    Review of Jacobs and Potter, hate crimes: Criminal law and identity politics (review)
    Journal of Homosexuality 45 (1): 152-159. 2003.
    This is a review of Hate Crimes: Criminal Law and Identity Politics, by James B. Jacobs and Kimberly Potter; it is argued that the arguments of that book completely fail to establish the book's principal conclusions.
  •  47
    Hierocles' Concentric Circles
    Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 62 (Summer 2022): 293-332. 2023.
    Hierocles, a Stoic of the second century CE, famously deployed an image of the ‘concentric circles’ that surround each of us. The image should not be read as advocating absolute impartiality (in the style of classical utilitarianism) or as illustrating the Stoic theory of oikeiōsis. Instead, it is designed to illustrate how it is ‘appropriate to act’ in certain cases. Like other Stoics, Hierocles bases his investigation of appropriate acts on what is ‘in accordance with nature’. According to his…Read more
  •  45
    Value Judgement: Improving Our Ethical Beliefs (review)
    Philosophical Review 107 (3): 447. 1998.
    This is a review of James Griffin's book "Value-Judgement: Improving Our Ethical Beliefs".
  •  43
    Can our reasons determine what it is rational for us to believe?
    Philosophical Studies (2-3): 1-10. 2023.
    This is a discussion of Mark Schroeder’s book Reasons First. In this book, Schroeder defends the following thesis: for every believer and every time, it is the reasons that the believer has at that time that determine what it is rational for the believer to believe at that time. It is argued here that this thesis is false, since it conflicts with the plausible principle of “normative invariance”: what a believer ought to believe at a time cannot depend on what the believer actually believes at t…Read more
  •  37
    How Can "Evidence" Be Normative?
    In Maria Lasonen-Aarnio & Clayton Littlejohn (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Evidence, Routledge. pp. 74-90. 2024.
    It is widely assumed that our “evidence” is at least one source of the “justification” that we have for believing things—where this notion of “justification” seems to be a normative notion. More precisely, it seems to be an agential normative notion, evaluating the different possible attitudes that are available to an agent at a time, on the basis of facts that are just “given”—that is, facts that it is not available to the agent to change through the way in which she exercises her reasoning cap…Read more
  •  32
    Rationality and Belief
    Oxford University Press. 2023.
    This book gives a general theory of rational belief. Although it can be read by itself, is a sequel to the author's previous book The Value of Rationality (Oxford, 2017). It takes the general conception of rationality that was defended in that earlier book, and combines it with an account of the varieties of belief, and of what it is for these beliefs to count as "correct", to develop an account of what it is for beliefs to count as rational. According to this account, rationality comes in degre…Read more
  •  32
    The Predicament of Choice
    Oxford Studies in Metaethics 12 294-313. 2017.
    Normal agents in the actual world are limited: they cannot think about all the options that are available to them—or even about all options that are available to them according to their evidence. Moreover, agents cannot choose an option unless they have thought about that option. Such agents can be irrational in two ways: either by making their choice too quickly, without canvassing enough options, or by wasting time canvassing ever more options when they have already thought of enough options. …Read more
  •  29
    White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice (review)
    Philosophical Review 104 (1): 156. 1995.
    This is a review of Ruth Garrett Millikan's 1993 book, White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice.
  •  26
    Review of "The Common Mind: An Essay on Psychology, Society, and Politics" by Philip Pettit (review)
    European Journal of Philosophy 4 (1): 111-115. 1996.
    This is a review of Philip Pettit's book "The Common Mind: An Essay on Psychology, Society, and Politics"
  •  21
    Christopher Peacocke’s The Realm of Reason (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74 (3): 776-791. 2007.
    This is a review of Christopher Peacocke's book The Realm of Reason (Oxford University Press, 2004).
  •  13
    Can our reasons determine what it is rational for us to believe?
    Philosophical Studies 181 (2): 627-636. 2023.
    This is a discussion of Mark Schroeder’s book Reasons First. In this book, Schroeder defends the following thesis: for every believer and every time, it is the reasons that the believer has at that time that determine what it is rational for the believer to believe at that time. It is argued here that this thesis is false, since it conflicts with the plausible principle of “normative invariance”: what a believer ought to believe at a time cannot depend on what the believer actually believes at t…Read more
  •  10
    The sources of moral knowledge
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 107 (2): 561-567. 2023.
  •  6
    Critical Notice of Jean Hampton, "The Authority of Reason" (review)
    Philosophical Books 40 (4): 218-226. 1999.
    This is a review of Jean Hampton's posthumously published book "The Authority of Reason" (Cambridge University Press, 1998).