•  16
    Strukturelle Rationalität, Gründe und Irrtumsszenarien (review)
    Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 68 (3): 472-480. 2020.
  •  25
    Immanuel Kant and Henry Sidgwick are towering figures in the history of moral philosophy. Kant's views on ethics continue to be discussed and studied in detail not only in philosophy, but also theology, political science, and legal theory. Meanwhile, Sidgwick is emerging as the philosopher within the utilitarian tradition who merits the same meticulous treatment that Kant receives. As champions of deontology and consequentialism respectively, Kant and Sidgwick disagree on many important issues. …Read more
  • „Traditionelle und nicht-reduktive kritische Theorie”
    Allgemeine Zeitschrift für Philosophie 31 (3): 261-280. 2006.
  •  2
    Arguments for moral consequentialism often appeal to an alleged structural similarity between consequentialist reasoning in ethics and rational decision-making in everyday life. Ordinary rational decision-making is seen as a paradigmatic case of goal-oriented, teleological decision-making, since it allegedly aims at maximizing the goal of preference satisfaction. This chapter describes and discusses a neglected type of preference change, “predictable preference accommodation.” This phenomenon le…Read more
  •  244
    Moral Realism and Two-Dimensional Semantics
    Ethics 121 (4): 717-748. 2011.
    Moral realists can, and should, allow that the truth-conditional content of moral judgments is in part attitudinal. I develop a two-dimensional semantics that embraces attitudinal content while preserving realist convictions about the independence of moral facts from our attitudes. Relative to worlds “considered as counterfactual,” moral terms rigidly track objective, response-independent properties. But relative to different ways the actual world turns out to be, they nonrigidly track whatever …Read more
  •  2521
    From Choice to Chance? Saving People, Fairness, and Lotteries
    Philosophical Review 124 (2): 169-206. 2015.
    Many authors in ethics, economics, and political science endorse the Lottery Requirement, that is, the following thesis: where different parties have equal moral claims to one indivisible good, it is morally obligatory to let a fair lottery decide which party is to receive the good. This article defends skepticism about the Lottery Requirement. It distinguishes three broad strategies of defending such a requirement: the surrogate satisfaction account, the procedural account, and the ideal consen…Read more
  • Epistemic Virtues (edited book)
    with David Schweikard
    . 2012.
  •  11
    On What Matters, 2 Bände by Derek Parfit (review)
    Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 66 (2): 335-339. 2012.
  •  75
    From A Rational Point Of View
    Oxford University Press. 2018.
    When we discuss normative reasons, oughts, requirements of rationality, hypothetical imperatives (or “anankastic conditionals”), motivating reasons and so on, we often use verbs like “believe” and “want” to capture a relevant subject’s perspective. According to the received view about sentences involving these verbs, what they do is describe the subject’s mental states. Many puzzles concerning normative discourse have to do with the role that mental states consequently appear to play in this dis…Read more
  •  98
    Kant und die Logik des "Ich denke"
    Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 64 (3): 331-356. 2010.
    This paper explores Kant’s views about the logical form of “I think”-judgments. It is shown that according to Kant, in an important class of cases the prefix “I think” does not contribute to the assertoric, truth-conditional content of judgments of the form “I think that P.” Thus, judgments of this type are often merely judgments that P. The prefix “I think” does mention the subject and his thought, but it does not make the complex judgment a judgment about the subject and his or her thought. Ka…Read more
  •  153
    Normative Reasons Contextualism
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 88 (3): 593-624. 2014.
    This article argues for the view that statements about normative reasons are context-sensitive. Specifically, they are sensitive to a contextual parameter specifying a relevant person's or group's body of information. The argument for normative reasons contextualism starts from the context-sensitivity of the normative “ought” and the further premise that reasons must be aligned with oughts. It is incoherent, I maintain, to suppose that someone normatively ought to φ but has most reason not to φ.…Read more
  •  44
    Strukturelle Entfremdung als Kategorie der Wirtschaftsethik
    Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 60 (2): 213-226. 2012.
    This paper argues that a certain kind of alienation from labour can be analyzed and explained in the theoretical framework that is dominant in current economics. Given a neoclassical model of a labour market, the intrinsic value that different kinds of labour may have for people can be represented as a source of utility (in the technical sense). It can then be shown that in capitalist economies, basing one’s supply decisions on this intrinsic value is predictably costly. So in the long run, rati…Read more