•  123
    Selection and explanation
    In Rethinking Explanation, Springer. pp. 131--136. 2006.
    Selection explanations explain some non-accidental generalizations in virtue of a selection process. Such explanations are not particulaizable - they do not transfer as explanations of the instances of such generalizations. This is unlike many explanations in the physical sciences, where the explanation of the general fact also provides an explanation of its instances (i.e. standard D-N explanations). Are selection explanations (e.g. in biology) therefore a different kind of explanation? I argue…Read more
  •  121
    Kuhn, naturalism, and the positivist legacy
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 35 (2): 337-356. 2004.
    I defend against criticism the following claims concening Thomas Kuhn: (i) there is a strong naturalist streak in The structure of scientific revolutions, whereby Kuhn used the results of a posteriori enquiry in addressing philosophical questions; (ii) as Kuhn's career as a philosopher of science developed he tended to drop the naturalistic elements and to replace them with more traditionally philosophical a prior approaches; (iii) at the same there is a significant residue of positivist thought…Read more
  •  118
    Review: Science, truth, and democracy (review)
    Mind 112 (448): 746-749. 2003.
  •  116
    Remarks on our knowledge of modal facts
    Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift 43 (1): 54--60. 2008.
    Can we have a posteriori knowledge of modal facts? And if so, is that knowledge fundamentally a posteriori, or does a priori intuition provide the modal component of what is known? Though the latter view seems more straightforward, there are also reasons for taking the first option seriously.
  •  107
    Kripke
    In Christopher Belshaw & Gary Kemp (eds.), 12 Modern Philosophers, Wiley-blackwell. pp. 153--72. 2009.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Introduction Necessity and Essence Naming and Reference Rules and Meaning Conclusion References.
  •  106
    Inductive knowledge
    In D. Pritchard (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Epistemology, Routledge. 2009.
    The first obstacle that confronts the student of induction is that of defining the subject matter. One initial point is to note that much of the relevant subject matter goes under the description ‘the theory of confirmation’. The distinction is primarily that the study of induction concerns inference, i.e. cases where one takes the conclusion to be established by the evidence, whereas confirmation concerns the weight of evidence, which one may take to be something like the credibility of a hypot…Read more
  •  101
    Natural kinds
    with Emma Tobin
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2009.
  •  93
    Internalism, Externalism, and the KK Principle
    Erkenntnis 86 (6): 1-20. 2019.
    This paper examines the relationship between the KK principle and the epistemological theses of externalism and internalism. In particular we examine arguments from Okasha :80–86, 2013) and Greco :169–197, 2014) which deny that we can derive the denial of the KK principle from externalism.
  •  93
    The logic in logicism
    Dialogue 36 (2): 341--60. 1997.
    Frege's logicism consists of two theses: the truths of arithmetic are truths of logic; the natural numbers are objects. In this paper I pose the question: what conception of logic is required to defend these theses? I hold that there exists an appropriate and natural conception of logic in virtue of which Hume's principle is a logical truth. Hume's principle, which states that the number of Fs is the number of Gs iff the concepts F and G are equinumerous is the central plank in the neo-logicist …Read more
  •  91
    The aim of belief and the aim of science
    Theoria. An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science 34 (2): 171. 2019.
    I argue that the constitutive aim of belief and the constitutive aim of science are both knowledge. The ‘aim of belief’, understood as the correctness conditions of belief, is to be identified with the product of properly functioning cognitive systems. Science is an institution that is the social functional analogue of a cognitive system, and its aim is the same as that of belief. In both cases it is knowledge rather than true belief that is the product of proper functioning.
  •  89
    In this article I take a loose, functional approach to defining induction: Inductive forms of reasoning include those prima facie reasonable inference patterns that one finds in science and elsewhere that are not clearly deductive. Inductive inference is often taken to be reasoning from the observed to the unobserved. But that is incorrect, since the premises of inductive inferences may themselves be the results of prior inductions. A broader conception of inductive inference regards any ampliat…Read more
  •  86
    Understanding the Replication Crisis as a Base Rate Fallacy
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 72 (4): 965-993. 2021.
    The replication (replicability, reproducibility) crisis in social psychology and clinical medicine arises from the fact that many apparently well-confirmed experimental results are subsequently overturned by studies that aim to replicate the original study. The culprit is widely held to be poor science: questionable research practices, failure to publish negative results, bad incentives, and even fraud. In this article I argue that the high rate of failed replications is consistent with high-qua…Read more
  •  82
    … And Then Again, He Might Not Be
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 87 (3): 517-521. 2009.
    In reply to Michael Bertrand, I clarify my view that the problem of physical evil is not an a priori problem but an a posteriori one
  •  80
    Fred Gifford (ed.): Philosophy of Medicine (review)
    Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 34 (1): 53-57. 2013.
  •  79
    Restricted Composition is Information Compression
    Philosophical Quarterly 73 (3): 677-700. 2023.
    This paper proposes and examines an answer to the special composition question—complex objects compress information about their parts. I start by defending fastenation for material objects and then extract from fastenation the idea that the conjoinment of parts establishes correlations among the locations and motions of those parts. I move from this to the proposal that entities are parts of some object when that object allows for the efficient, if lossy, compression of information about those p…Read more
  •  75
  •  71
    Looking for laws
    Metascience 15 441-54. 2006.
    Metascience 15 (2006) 441-54
  •  70
    Introduction
    Synthese 149 (3): 445-450. 2006.
    This volume contains essays by five British philosophers and one Swedish philosopher working in metaphysics and in particular metaphysics as it relates to the philosophy of science. These philosophers are the core of a tight network of European philosophers of science and metaphysicians and their essays have evolved as a result of workshops in Lund, Edinburgh, and Athens.
  •  68
    Squaring the circle: Hobbes on philosophy and geometry
    Journal of the History of Ideas 57 (2). 1996.
    Hobbes ' geometrical disputes are significant since they highlight several important strands in his thought - issues concerning the right to make definitions, his anti-clericalism, the maker's knowledge argument and his objections to algebra. These are examined, and the foundational position, according to Hobbes, of geomentry in relation to philosophy, science and technology, explained and discussed
  •  67
    Review. The metaphysics of science. C Dilworth
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48 (2): 284-286. 1997.
  •  67
    Referring to Natural Kind Thingamajigs, and What They Are: A Reply to Needham
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 26 (1): 103-109. 2012.
    Natural kind terms appear to behave like singular terms. If they were genuine singular terms, appearing in true sentences, that would be some reason to believe that there are entities to which the terms refer, the natural kinds. Paul Needham has attacked my arguments that natural kind terms are singular, referring expressions. While conceding the correctness of some of his criticisms, I defend and expand on the underlying view in this paper. I also briefly sketch an account of what natural kinds…Read more
  •  66
    Further antidotes: A response to Gundersen
    Philosophical Quarterly 50 (199): 229-233. 2000.
    In my 'Dispositions and Antidotes', The Philosophical Quarterly, 48 (1998), I raise an objection to the conditional analysis of dispositions, both in its simple formulation and in a more sophisticated version due to David Lewis, The Philosophical Quarterly, 47 (1997). The objection suggests that a disposition may be continuously present and the appropriate stimulus occur without the manifestation occurring, because some outside influence, an antidote, interferes. Gundersen in The Philosophical Q…Read more
  •  65
    Internalism, Externalism, and the KK Principle
    Erkenntnis 86 (6): 1713-1732. 2019.
    This paper examines the relationship between the KK principle and the epistemological theses of externalism and internalism. In particular we examine arguments from Okasha (Analysis 73(1):80–86, 2013) and Greco (J Philos 111(4):169–197, 2014) which deny that we can derive the denial of the KK principle from externalism.
  •  63
  •  59
    Philosophy of Science
    Mind 109 (434): 325-327. 2000.
  •  57
    Understanding disease and illness
    Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 38 (4): 239-244. 2017.
  •  56
    This volume contains essays by five British philosophers and one Swedish philosopher working in metaphysics and in particular metaphysics as it relates to the philosophy of science. These philosophers are the core of a tight network of European philosophers of science and metaphysicians and their essays have evolved as a result of workshops in Lund, Edinburgh, and Athens.