-
33Ware liefde zonder uniciteit: goede redenen voor romantische liefdeAlgemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 107 (1): 71-93. 2015.True Love Without Uniqueness: Good Reasons for Romantic Love Love involves emotions, and emotions are things that happen to us. So how can love be true? Love can be true only if people can have reasons for loving someone. I explore the tension between these two thoughts and propose a way of resolving it. I argue that reasons for romantic love are not limited to the other person’s properties, not even when relational properties such as a common sense of humour are included. A full-blown romantic …Read more
-
1British classical economists and their methodological heritage A review of Deborah A. Redman's The Rise of Political Economy as a Science. Methodology and the Classical Economists (review)Journal of Economic Methodology 8 (1): 145-152. 2001.
-
63Social Ontology: Collective Intentionality and Group Agents, Raimo Tuomela. Oxford University Press, 2013, xiv + 310 pages (review)Economics and Philosophy 31 (2): 341-348. 2015.
-
122Making the Social World: The Structure of Human Civilization, John R. Searle, Oxford University Press, 2010, 224 pages (review)Economics and Philosophy 27 (3): 338-346. 2011.
-
163False models as explanatory enginesPhilosophy of the Social Sciences 38 (3): 334-360. 2008.Many models in economics are very unrealistic. At the same time, economists put a lot of effort into making their models more realistic. I argue that in many cases, including the Modigliani-Miller irrelevance theorem investigated in this paper, the purpose of this process of concretization is explanatory. When evaluated in combination with their assumptions, a highly unrealistic model may well be true. The purpose of relaxing an unrealistic assumption, then, need not be to move from a false mode…Read more
-
144Control, intentional action, and moral responsibilityPhilosophical Psychology 24 (6). 2011.Skill or control is commonly regarded as a necessary condition for intentional action. This received wisdom is challenged by experiments conducted by Joshua Knobe and Thomas Nadelhoffer, which suggest that moral considerations sometimes trump considerations of skill and control. I argue that this effect (as well as the Knobe effect) can be explained in terms of the role normative reasons play in the concept of intentional action. This explanation has significant advantages over its rivals. It in…Read more
-
270The location problem in social ontologySynthese 190 (3): 413-437. 2013.Mental, mathematical, and moral facts are difficult to accommodate within an overall worldview due to the peculiar kinds of properties inherent to them. In this paper I argue that a significant class of social entities also presents us with an ontological puzzle that has thus far not been addressed satisfactorily. This puzzle relates to the location of certain social entities. Where, for instance, are organizations located? Where their members are, or where their designated offices are? Organiza…Read more
-
213A unified social ontologyPhilosophical Quarterly 65 (259): 177-201. 2015.Current debates in social ontology are dominated by approaches that view institutions either as rules or as equilibria of strategic games. We argue that these two approaches can be unified within an encompassing theory based on the notion of correlated equilibrium. We show that in a correlated equilibrium each player follows a regulative rule of the form ‘if X then do Y’. We then criticize Searle's claim that constitutive rules of the form ‘X counts as Y in C’ are fundamental building blocks for…Read more
-
Review of Russell Hardin’s How do you know?: the economics of ordinary knowledge (review)Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics 3 (1): 93-97. 2010.
-
244Intentional action and the praise-blame asymmetryPhilosophical Quarterly 58 (233): 630-641. 2008.Recent empirical research by Joshua Knobe has uncovered two asymmetries in judgements about intentional action and moral responsibility. First, people are more inclined to say that a side effect was brought about intentionally when they regard that side effect as bad than when they regard it as good. Secondly, people are more inclined to ascribe blame to someone for bad effects than they are inclined to ascribe praise for good effects. These findings suggest that the notion of intentional action…Read more
-
69Deconstructing Searle’s Making the Social WorldPhilosophy of the Social Sciences 45 (3): 363-369. 2015.Hindriks argued that Searle’s theory of institutions suffers from a number of problems pertaining to the notions of constitutive rule, status function, Status Function Declaration, deontic power, and human right. Lobo argues that these criticisms are not sufficiently charitable. In response, it is argued here that the problems that were identified earlier are sufficiently severe to call for substantial revisions of the theory
-
94In the literature on social ontology, two perspectives on collective agency have been developed. The first is the internal perspective, the second the external one. The internal perspective takes the point of view of the members as its point of departure and appeals, inter alia, to the joint intentions they form. The idea is that collective agents perform joint actions such as dancing the tango, organizing prayer meetings, or performing symphonies. Such actions are generated by joint intentions,…Read more
-
116But Where Is the University?Dialectica 66 (1): 93-113. 2012.Famously Ryle imagined a visitor who has seen the colleges, departments, and libraries of a university but still wonders where the university is. The visitor fails to realize that the university consists of these organizational units. In this paper I ask what exactly the relation is between institutional entities such as universities and the entities they are composed of. I argue that the relation is constitution, and that it can be illuminated in terms of constitutive rules. The understanding o…Read more
-
160The freedom of collective agentsJournal of Political Philosophy 16 (2). 2007.Corporate freedom is the freedom of a collective agent to perform a joint action. According to a reductive account, a collective or corporate agent is free exactly if the individuals who constitute the corporate agent are free. It is argued that individual freedoms are neither necessary nor sufficient for corporate freedom. The alternative account proposed here focuses on the performance of the joint action by the corporate agent itself. Subsequently, the analysis is applied to Cohen’s (1983) an…Read more
-
Opzet en morele veranbvoordelijkheid in de experimentele filosofieAlgemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 101 (1): 49-55. 2009.
-
114How Autonomous Are Collective Agents? Corporate Rights and Normative IndividualismErkenntnis 79 (S9): 1565-1585. 2014.Corporate responsibility requires a conception of collective agency on which collective agents are able to form moral judgments and act on them. In spite of claims to the contrary, existing accounts of collective agency fall short of this kind of corporate autonomy, as they fail to explain how collective agents might be responsive to moral reasons. I discuss how a recently proposed conception of shared valuing can be used for developing a solution to this problem. Although the resulting concepti…Read more
-
159Corporate responsibility and judgment aggregationEconomics and Philosophy 25 (2): 161-177. 2009.Paradoxical results concerning judgment aggregation have recently been invoked to defend the thesis that a corporate agent can be morally responsible for a decision without any of its individual members bearing such responsibility. I contend that the arguments offered for this irreducibility thesis are inconclusive. They do not pay enough attention to how we evaluate individual moral responsibility, in particular not to the role that a flawed assessment of the normative reasons that bear on the …Read more
-
92Acceptance-dependence: A social kind of response-dependencePacific Philosophical Quarterly 87 (4). 2006.Neither Johnston's nor Wright's account of response-dependence offers a complete picture of response-dependence, as they do not apply to all concepts that are intrinsically related to our mental responses. In order to (begin to) remedy this situation, a new conception of response-dependence is introduced that I call "acceptance-dependence". This account applies to concepts such as goal, constitutional, and money, the first two of which have mistakenly been taken to be response-dependent in anoth…Read more
-
319Restructuring Searle’s Making the Social WorldPhilosophy of the Social Sciences 43 (3): 373-389. 2013.Institutions are normative social structures that are collectively accepted. In his book Making the Social World, John R. Searle maintains that these social structures are created and maintained by Status Function Declarations. The article’s author criticizes this claim and argues, first, that Searle overestimates the role that language plays in relation to institutions and, second, that Searle’s notion of a Status Function Declaration confuses more than it enlightens. The distinction is exposed…Read more
Areas of Specialization
Philosophy of Action |
Social and Political Philosophy |
Metaphysics and Epistemology |
Areas of Interest
Philosophy of Social Science |
Metaphysics and Epistemology |
Other Academic Areas |