•  608
    Climate Models, Calibration, and Confirmation
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 64 (3): 609-635. 2013.
    We argue that concerns about double-counting—using the same evidence both to calibrate or tune climate models and also to confirm or verify that the models are adequate—deserve more careful scrutiny in climate modelling circles. It is widely held that double-counting is bad and that separate data must be used for calibration and confirmation. We show that this is far from obviously true, and that climate scientists may be confusing their targets. Our analysis turns on a Bayesian/relative-likelih…Read more
  •  147
    The Scientist qua Policy Advisor Makes Value Judgments
    Philosophy of Science 79 (5): 893-904. 2012.
    Richard Rudner famously argues that the communication of scientific advice to policy makers involves ethical value judgments. His argument has, however, been rightly criticized. This article revives Rudner’s conclusion, by strengthening both his lines of argument: we generalize his initial assumption regarding the form in which scientists must communicate their results and complete his ‘backup’ argument by appealing to the difference between private and public decisions. Our conclusion that scie…Read more
  •  10
    No Title available: Reviews
    Economics and Philosophy 25 (2): 236-242. 2009.
  •  99
    Uncertainty, Learning, and the “Problem” of Dilation
    Erkenntnis 79 (6): 1287-1303. 2014.
    Imprecise probabilism—which holds that rational belief/credence is permissibly represented by a set of probability functions—apparently suffers from a problem known as dilation. We explore whether this problem can be avoided or mitigated by one of the following strategies: (a) modifying the rule by which the credal state is updated, (b) restricting the domain of reasonable credal states to those that preclude dilation
  •  27
    Review of Husain Sarkar, Group Rationality in Scientific Research (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2007 (10). 2007.
  •  101
    I focus my discussion on the well-known Ellsberg paradox. I find good normative reasons for incorporating non-precise belief, as represented by sets of probabilities, in an Ellsberg decision model. This amounts to forgoing the completeness axiom of expected utility theory. Provided that probability sets are interpreted as genuinely indeterminate belief, such a model can moreover make the “Ellsberg choices” rationally permissible. Without some further element to the story, however, the model does…Read more
  •  73
    Daniel steel philosophy and the precautionary principle: Science, evidence, and environmental policy
    with Camilla Colombo
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 67 (4): 1195-1200. 2016.
  •  21
    Review of Preference and Information (review)
    Economics and Philosophy 25 (2): 236-242. 2009.
  •  208
    Model tuning in engineering: uncovering the logic
    Journal of Strain Analysis for Engineering Design 51 (1): 63-71. 2015.
    In engineering, as in other scientific fields, researchers seek to confirm their models with real-world data. It is common practice to assess models in terms of the distance between the model outputs and the corresponding experimental observations. An important question that arises is whether the model should then be ‘tuned’, in the sense of estimating the values of free parameters to get a better fit with the data, and furthermore whether the tuned model can be confirmed with the same data used…Read more
  •  277
    This paper considers a puzzling conflict between two positions that are each compelling: it is irrational for an agent to pay to avoid `free' evidence before making a decision, and rational agents may have imprecise beliefs and/or desires. Indeed, we show that Good's theorem concerning the invariable choice-worthiness of free evidence does not generalise to the imprecise realm, given the plausible existing decision theories for handling imprecision. A key ingredient in the analysis, and a potent…Read more