•  48
    Hegel on Political Philosophy and Political Actuality
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 53 (5): 401-416. 2010.
    Hegel is the most prominent philosopher who argued that 'philosophy is its own time comprehended in thought', and he argued for this with an elaborate theory about the necessarily historical and experiential content of normative principles and ideals, especially, in his own historical period, the ideal of a free life. His insistence that philosophy must attend to the 'actuality' of the norms it considers is quite controversial, often accused of accommodation with the status quo, a 'might makes r…Read more
  •  32
    Horstmann, Siep, and German Idealism
    European Journal of Philosophy 2 (1): 85-96. 1994.
    Die Grenzen der Vernunft. Eine Untersuchung zu Zielen und Motiven des Deutschen Idealismus. By Rolf‐Peter Horstmann. Frankfurt a.M.: Anton Hain, 1991, 321 pp. ISBN 3–445‐08568‐4Praktische Philosophie im Deutschen Idealismus. By Ludwig Siep. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp, 1992, 348 pp. ISBN 3–518‐28635‐8 pb
  •  1
    How to overcome oneself: Nietzsche on freedom
    In Ken Gemes & Simon May (eds.), Nietzsche on Freedom and Autonomy, Oxford University Press. pp. 69. 2009.
  •  32
    Hegelianism as modernism
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 38 (3). 1995.
    No abstract
  •  26
    Review of Richard Eldridge, Literature, Life, and Modernity (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2009 (1). 2009.
  • On giving oneself the law
    In Richard L. Velkley (ed.), Freedom and the Human Person, Catholic University of America Press. 2007.
  •  33
    Review of Rudiger Bittner, Doing Things for Reasons (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2002 (7). 2002.
  •  117
    The affirmation of life: Nietzsche on overcoming nihilism
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77 (1): 281-291. 2008.
    No Abstract
  •  6
    Nietzsche described all modern moral philosophy, together with its psychological assumptions, as a doomed attempt to cling to the fundamental precepts of Christian morality, but without the authorizing force that made the whole “system” credible – a creator God. He understood this morality as essentially an egalitarian humanism, opposed to all forms of egoism or inequality and one promoting a selfless dedication to a perspective where one would count equally, as only “one among many,” in any ref…Read more
  •  2
    Online Publication Date: 01 September 2007 To cite this Article: Pippin, Robert (2007) 'Can There Be 'Unprincipled Virtue'? Comments on Nomy Arpaly', Philosophical Explorations, 10:3, 291 - 301 To link to this article: DOI: 10.1080/13869790701535360 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13869790701535360..
  •  4
    dimension is actually “the typical.”[i] There would seem to be little typical about a world of comatose women, a barely sane, largely delusional male nurse, a woman bullfighter, and a rape that leads to a “rebirth” in a number of senses. But comatose women, the central figures in Almodóvar’s Talk to Her, are, oddly, very familiar in that mythological genre closest to us: fairy tales. Both Snow White and Sleeping Beauty are comatose women who endure, “non-consensually” we must say, a male kiss, m…Read more
  •  134
    What was abstract art? (From the point of view of hegel)
    In Stephen Houlgate (ed.), Hegel and the Arts, Northwestern University Press. pp. 1-24. 2007.
    The emergence of abstract art, first in the early part of the century with Kandinsky, Malevich, and Mondrian, and then in the much more celebrated case of America in the fifties (Rothko, Pollock, and others) remains puzzling. Such a great shift in aesthetic standards and taste is not only unprecedented in its radicality. The fact that nonfigurative art, without identifiable content in any traditional sense, was produced, appreciated, and, finally, eagerly bought and, even, finally, triumphantly …Read more
  •  331
    Hegel's social theory of agency : the 'inner-outer' problem
    In Arto Laitinen & Constantine Sandis (eds.), Hegel on Action, Palgrave-macmillan. pp. 3-50. 2010.
    The following is a chapter of a book and I should say something at the outset about the content of the book. The topic is Hegel’s “social theory of agency,” and that topic, given how the problem of agency is usually understood, raises the immediate question of why anyone would think that “sociality” would have anything at all to do with the “problem of agency.” That problem is understood in a number of ways; most generally – what distinguishes naturally occurring events from actions (if anything…Read more
  •  5
    As a representative of the humanities, I understood my charge this afternoon to be to offer some sort of response to what is at the very least a book publishing or market phenomenon – the flood of recent books especially in the last decade by neuroscientists, primatologists, computer scientists, evolutionary biologists and economists about what had traditionally been considered issues in the humanities - issues like morality, politics, the nature of rationality, what makes a response to an objec…Read more
  •  126
    Philosophy is its own time comprehended in thought
    Topoi 25 (1-2): 85-90. 2006.
    So much philosophy is so unavoidably guided by intuitions, and such intuitions are so formed by examples, and such examples must of necessity present so cropped and abstract a picture of an instance or event or decision, that, left to its traditional methods, philosophy might be ill-equipped on its own to answer a question about the true content of an historical ideal like ``autonomy'', or authenticity or ``leading a free life''. One needs to bring so many factors into play at once that one non-…Read more
  •  80
    Can there be 'unprincipled virtue'? Comments on Nomy Arpaly
    Philosophical Explorations 10 (3). 2007.
    In her book, Unprincipled Virtue, Nomy Arpaly is suspicious of reflective endorsement or deliberative rationality views of agency, those which tie the possibility of responsibility and moral blame to the conscious exercise of deliberation and reflection, and which require as a condition of blame- or praise- worthiness an agent's explicit commitment to ethical principles. I am in sympathy with her attack on standard autonomy theories, but argue that she confuses the phenomenon of unknowing and un…Read more
  •  17
    Author's précis of Henry James and modern moral life
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 45 (3). 2002.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  20
    Responses to Conway, Mooney, and Rorty
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 45 (3). 2002.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  6
    In this pathbreaking book one of America’s most distinguished philosophers brilliantly explores the status and authority of law and the nature of political allegiance through close readings of three classic Hollywood Westerns: Howard Hawks’ _Red River_ and John Ford’s _The Man Who Shot Liberty Valance_ and _The Searchers._ Robert Pippin treats these films as sophisticated mythic accounts of a key moment in American history: its “second founding,” or the western expansion. His central question co…Read more
  •  138
    The Status of Literature in Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit
    In Richard T. Gray, Nicholas Halmi, Gary Handwerk, Michael A. Rosenthal & Klaus Vieweg (eds.), Inventions of the Imagination: Interdisciplinary Perspectives on the Imaginary since Romanticism, University of Washington Press. 2011.
    Hegel, in a chapter called “Absolute Knowing,” end his most exciting and original work, the Jena Phenomenology of Spirit, with a quotation, or rather a significant misquotation, of a poet? The poet is Schiller and the poem is his 1782 “Freundschaft” (Friendship). This immediately turns into two questions: Why are the last words not Hegel’s own, and why are they rather a poet’s? I will turn to the details in a moment but, as noted, such an inquiry may not be worth the trouble. Authors, even philo…Read more
  •  5
    Henry James and Modern Moral Life
    Cambridge University Press. 1999.
    This important book argues that Henry James reveals in his fiction a sophisticated theory of moral understanding and moral motivation. The claim is that in his novels and short stories James is engaged in a distinctive kind of original thinking and reflecting on modern moral life. Sensitive to the precarious and extremely confusing situation of moral understanding in modern societies, James avoids skepticism and presents powerfully the full nature of moral claims and moral dependence. The book i…Read more
  •  39
    Response to David Kolb
    The Owl of Minerva 30 (2): 277-286. 1999.
  •  75
    Nietzsche and the origin of the idea of modernism
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 26 (2). 1983.
    The notion of modernism, originally a classificatory term in art and literary criticism, now a common term of art in many philosophic (and anti?philosophic) programs, has remained an elusive, often vague point of view. For a discussion of the notion's historical accuracy and philosophic legitimacy this article selects an author greatly responsible for setting out the problem (called by him ?nihilism') and philosophically sensitive to the issues involved in claiming that something essential to a …Read more
  •  244
    Brandom's Hegel
    European Journal of Philosophy 13 (3). 2005.
  •  5
    ¿Lo mío y lo tuyo? El Estado kantiano
    Anuario Filosófico 37 (80): 595-630. 2004.
    Kant says there is a duty to exit the state of nature, to enter into a civil state. He says this is a duty of right, not a duty of virtue. The article discusses the argument he gives to support this view, as well as the contemporary discussion on the relationship between this duty of right and the categorical imperative. The discussion is full of implications. Particularly significant is the view of the Kantian state emerging from it, which challenges the conventional account: instead of a state…Read more