•  9
    Existence: Two Dogmas of Analysis
    In Daniel Novotný & Lukáš Novák (eds.), Neo-Aristotelian Perspectives in Metaphysics, Routledge. pp. 45-75. 2013.
    Analytic philosophy of existence in the 20th century and beyond has been dominated by two central claims. One is that existence is instantiation. The other is that there are no modes of existence. This article attempts to refute both claims.
  •  346
    Hugh McCann on the Implications of Divine Sovereignty
    American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 88 (1): 149-161. 2014.
    This review article summarizes and in part criticizes Hugh J. McCann’s detailed elaboration of the consequences of the idea that God is absolutely sovereign and thus unlimited in knowledge and power in his 2012 Creation and the Sovereignty of God. While there is much to agree with in McCann’s treatment, it is argued that divine sovereignty cannot extend as far as he would like to extend it. The absolute lord of the natural and moral orders cannot be absolutely sovereign over the conceptual and m…Read more
  •  157
    This review article explores in a critical spirit the differences between constituent and relational ontology as practiced by four contemporary Aristotelian philosophers, Michael J. Loux, E. J. Lowe, Lukáš Novák, and Stanislav Sousedík
  •  95
    Bradley’s Regress and Relation-Instances
    Modern Schoolman 81 (3): 159-183. 2004.
  •  42
    Existence and Indefinite Identifiability
    Southwest Philosophy Review 11 (2): 171-186. 1995.
  •  465
    Can the Chariot Take Us to the Land of No Self?
    The Proceedings of the Twenty-First World Congress of Philosophy 9 29-33. 2006.
    This paper examines a famous argument for the Buddhist doctrine of anatta ("no self) according to which nothing possesses self-nature or substantial reality. The argument unfolds during a debate between the monk Nagasena and King Milinda (Menandros). Nagasena's challenge to the King is that he demonstrate the substantial reality of the chariot in which he arrived at their meeting when said chariot is (i) not identical to any one of its proper parts, (ii) not identical to the mereological sum of …Read more
  •  152
    The Hume-Edwards Objection to the Cosmological Argument
    Journal of Philosophical Research 22 423-443. 1997.
    One sort of cosmological argument for the existence of God starts from the fact that the universe exists and argues to a transcendent cause of this fact. According to the Hume-Edwards objection to this sort of cosmological argument, if every member of the universe is caused by a preceding member, then the universe has an intemal causal explanation in such a way as to obviate the need for a transcendent cause. The Hume-Edwards objection has recently come under attack by atheists and theists alike…Read more
  •  57
    Do Individuals Exist?
    Journal of Philosophical Research 20 195-220. 1995.
    Is there room for a metaphysics of existence above and beyond the logic of ‘exists’? This paper defends an affirmative answer. It takes its point of departure from a recent polemic of Paul Edwards against Heidegger. According to Edwards, following Frege and Russell, Heidegger mistakenly assumes that existence belongs to individuals. I argue that although Heidegger does indeed make this assumption, he is not mistaken in so doing. My main concern, however, is neither to defend Heidegger nor to rep…Read more
  •  104
    Kant, Heidegger, and the Problem of the Thing in Itself
    International Philosophical Quarterly 23 (1): 35-43. 1983.
  •  39
  •  279
    Does the Cosmological Argument Depend on the Ontological?
    Faith and Philosophy 17 (4): 441-458. 2000.
    Does the cosmological argument (CA) depend on the ontological (OA)? That depends. If the OA is an argument “from mere concepts,” then no; if the OA is an argument from possibility, then yes. That is my main thesis. Along the way, I explore a number of subsidiary themes, among them, the nature of proof in metaphysics, and what Kant calls the “mystery of absolute necessity.”
  •  87
    Has the Ontological Argument Been Refuted?
    Religious Studies 29 (1). 1993.
    Suppose we say that a deductive argument is probative just in case it is valid in point of logical form, possesses true premises, and is free of informal fallacy. We can then say that an argument is normatively persuasive for a person if and only if it is both probative and has premises that can be accepted, without any breach of epistemic propriety, by the person in question. If the premises of a probative argument would be accepted by any reasonable person, I will call such an argument demonst…Read more
  •  105
    A Tension in Quine’s Theory of Existence
    Philo 6 (2): 193-204. 2003.
    According to Quine, the ontological question can be posed in three Anglo-Saxon monosyllables: “What is there?” But if we call this the ontological question, what shall we call the logically prior question: “What is it for an item to be there?” Peter van Inwagen has recently suggested that this be called the meta-ontological question, and more importantly, has endorsed Quine’s answer to it. Ingredient in this Quinean answer to the meta-ontological question are several theses, among them, “Being i…Read more
  •  88
    Incarnation and Identity
    Philo 5 (1): 84-93. 2002.
    The characteristic claim of Christianity, as codified at Chalcedon, is that God the Son, the second person of the Trinity, is numerically the same person as Jesus of Nazareth. This article raises three questions that appear to threaten the coherence of orthodox Chalcedonian incarnationalism. First, how can one person exemplify seemingly incompatible natures? Second, how can one person exemplify seemingly incompatible non-nature properties? Third, how can there be one person if the concept of inc…Read more
  •  62
    Relativism, Truth and the Symmetry Thesis
    The Monist 67 (3): 452-466. 1984.
    The interest and longevity of philosophical positions and arguments often seem to be an inverse function of the clarity with which these positions and arguments are articulated. Frequently, the most interesting positions are those pregnant with ambiguity and ever teetering on the brink of incoherence. Examples are not hard to find in the history of philosophy. Kant’s philosophy is full of them: the role and status of the Ding an sich; the proof-structure of the transcendental deduction of the ca…Read more
  •  64
    Heidegger’s Reduction of Being to Truth
    New Scholasticism 59 (2): 156-176. 1985.
  •  40
    Two Faces of Theism
    Idealistic Studies 20 (3): 238-257. 1990.
    Current debates in the analytic mainstream about the existence of God have often an air of the fantastic about them. Discussions of the God question typically begin with an inventory of properties definitive of the disputed entity and then proceed to a consideration of the question whether there is anything that answers to the definition. The theist adduces arguments to show, not so much that God actually exists—an enterprise much to bold for anyone laboring in the shadow of the Kantian Critique…Read more
  •  3061
    No Self?: A Look at a Buddhist Argument
    International Philosophical Quarterly 42 (4): 453-466. 2002.
    Central to Buddhist thought and practice is the anattā doctrine. In its unrestricted form the doctrine amounts to the claim that nothing at all possesses self-nature. This article examines an early Buddhist argument for the doctrine. The argument, roughly, is that (i) if anything were a self, it would be both unchanging and self-determining; (ii) nothing has both of these properties; therefore, (iii) nothing is a self. The thesis of this article is that, despite the appearance of formal validity…Read more
  •  71
    Concurrentism or Occasionalism?
    American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 70 (3): 339-359. 1996.
  •  83
    Could a Classical Theist Be a Physicalist?
    Faith and Philosophy 15 (2): 160-180. 1998.
    Since physicalism is fashionable nowadays, one should perhaps not be too surprised to find a growing number of theistic philosophers bent on combining theism with physicalism. I shall be arguing that this is an innovation we have good reason to resist. I begin by distinguishing global physicalism (physicalism about everything) from local physicalism (physicalism about human beings). I then present the theist who would be a physicalist with a challenge: Articulate a version of local physicalism t…Read more
  •  41
    The Problem of Existence by Arthur Witherall
    Philo 6 (1): 176-188. 2003.
  •  110
  •  52
    Brentano on Existence
    History of Philosophy Quarterly 18 (3): 311-327. 2001.
  •  141
    Could the universe cause itself to exist?
    Philosophy 75 (4): 604-612. 2000.
    This article responds to Quentin Smith's, ‘The Reason the Universe Exists is that it Caused Itself to Exist’, Philosophy 74 (1999), 579–586. My rejoinder makes three main points. The first is that Smith's argument for a finitely old, but causally self-explanatory, universe fails from probative overkill: if sound, it also shows that all manner of paltry event-sequences are causally self-explanatory.The second point is that the refutation of Smith's argument extends to Hume's argument for an infin…Read more
  •  143
    God, causation and occasionalism
    Religious Studies 35 (1): 3-18. 1999.
    The doctrine that there are no logically necessary connections in nature can be used to support both occasionalism, according to which God alone can be a cause, and 'anti-occasionalism', according to which God cannot be a cause. Quentin Smith has recently invoked the 'no logically necessary connections in nature' doctrine in support of the latter. I bring two main objections against his thesis that God (logically) cannot be a cause. The first is that there are good reasons to think that there ar…Read more
  •  79
    On traditional theism, God is not only a creator but also a conserver. The doctrine of conservation, however, appears to face a dilemma. Either conservation is continuous re-creation with consequences inimical to diachronic identity, or conservation is an operation upon a pre-existent entity, which, because it is pre-existent, is in no clear need of conservation. This article first makes a case for the dilemma, and then proposes a way between its horns. Safe passage is possible if we adopt prese…Read more
  •  22
    Book review (review)
    with Martin Andic
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 32 (1): 61-64. 1992.