•  113
    Truth
    Princeton University Press. 2011.
    This is a concise, advanced introduction to current philosophical debates about truth. A blend of philosophical and technical material, the book is organized around, but not limited to, the tendency known as deflationism, according to which there is not much to say about the nature of truth. In clear language, Burgess and Burgess cover a wide range of issues, including the nature of truth, the status of truth-value gaps, the relationship between truth and meaning, relativism and pluralism about …Read more
  •  96
    Dummett's case for intuitionism
    History and Philosophy of Logic 5 (2): 177-194. 1984.
    Dummett's case against platonism rests on arguments concerning the acquisition and manifestation of knowledge of meaning. Dummett's arguments are here criticized from a viewpoint less Davidsonian than Chomskian. Dummett's case against formalism is obscure because in its prescriptive considerations are not clearly separated from descriptive. Dummett's implicit value judgments are here made explicit and questioned. ?Combat Revisionism!? Chairman Mao
  •  95
    Supervaluations and the propositional attitude constraint
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 26 (1): 103-119. 1997.
    For the sentences of languages that contain operators that express the concepts of definiteness and indefiniteness, there is an unavoidable tension between a truth-theoretic semantics that delivers truth conditions for those sentences that capture their propositional contents and any model-theoretic semantics that has a story to tell about how indetifiniteness in a constituent affects the semantic value of sentences which imbed it. But semantic theories of both kinds play essential roles, so the…Read more
  •  88
    Error theories and values
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76 (4). 1998.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  85
    Marcus, Kripke, and names
    Philosophical Studies 84 (1). 1996.
  •  81
    A Subject with no Object
    Philosophical Review 108 (1): 106. 1999.
    This is the first systematic survey of modern nominalistic reconstructions of mathematics, and for this reason alone it should be read by everyone interested in the philosophy of mathematics and, more generally, in questions concerning abstract entities. In the bulk of the book, the authors sketch a common formal framework for nominalistic reconstructions, outline three major strategies such reconstructions can follow, and locate proposals in the literature with respect to these strategies. The …Read more
  •  78
    Phenomenal qualities and the nontransitivity of matching
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 68 (2): 206-220. 1990.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  78
    Natural deduction rules for a logic of vagueness
    with I. L. Humberstone
    Erkenntnis 27 (2): 197-229. 1987.
    Extant semantic theories for languages containing vague expressions violate intuition by delivering the same verdict on two principles of classical propositional logic: the law of noncontradiction and the law of excluded middle. Supervaluational treatments render both valid; many-Valued treatments, Neither. The core of this paper presents a natural deduction system, Sound and complete with respect to a 'mixed' semantics which validates the law of noncontradiction but not the law of excluded midd…Read more
  •  77
    Decidability for branching time
    Studia Logica 39 (2-3): 203-218. 1980.
    The species of indeterminist tense logic called Peircean by A. N. Prior is proved to be recursively decidable
  •  77
    3. Cats, Dogs, and so on
    In Dean W. Zimmerman (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, Oxford University Press. pp. 4--56. 2008.
  •  75
    Probability logic
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (2): 264-274. 1969.
    In this paper we introduce a system S5U, formed by adding to the modal system S5 a new connective U, Up being read “probably”. A few theorems are derived in S5U, and the system is provided with a decision procedure. Several decidable extensions of S5U are discussed, and probability logic is related to plurality quantification.
  •  74
    Hintikka et Sandu versus Frege in re Arbitrary Functions
    Philosophia Mathematica 1 (1): 50-65. 1993.
    Hintikka and Sandu have recently claimed that Frege's notion of function was substantially narrower than that prevailing in real analysis today. In the present note, their textual evidence for this claim is examined in the light of relevant historical and biographical background and judged insufficient.
  •  73
    Fixing Frege
    Princeton University Press. 2005.
    This book surveys the assortment of methods put forth for fixing Frege's system, in an attempt to determine just how much of mathematics can be reconstructed in ...
  •  73
    Discussion—Soames on Empiricism
    Philosophical Studies 129 (3): 619-626. 2006.
    Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century by Scott Soames reminds me of nothing so much as Lectures on Literature by Vladimir Nabokov. Both are works that arose immediately out of the needs of undergraduate teaching, yet each manages to say much of significance to knowledgeable professionals. Each indirectly provides an outline of the history of its field, through a presentation of selected major works, taken in chronological order and including items that are generally recognized as marki…Read more
  •  69
    Relevance: a fallacy?
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 22 (2): 97-104. 1981.
  •  69
    In defense of an indeterminist theory of vagueness
    The Monist 81 (1): 233--52. 1998.
    Regardless of the theory of vagueness we adhere to, we all agree that no facts, known or practically knowable, suffice to determine the location of precise boundaries for vague concepts. According to the epistemic theory of vagueness, this ignorance is entirely an epistemic matter—vague concepts have sharp boundaries but we can never know their exact locations. Opposed to epistemicism is a view—or family of views—I shall call indeterminism. The indeterminist agrees with the epistemicist that we …Read more
  •  69
    One textbook may introduce the real numbers in Cantor’s way, and another in Dedekind’s, and the mathematical community as a whole will be completely indifferent to the choice between the two. This sort of phenomenon was famously called to the attention of philosophers by Paul Benacerraf. It will be argued that structuralism in philosophy of mathematics is a mistake, a generalization of Benacerraf’s observation in the wrong direction, resulting from philosophers’ preoccupation with ontology.
  •  67
    Thomas McKay. Plural predication
    Philosophia Mathematica 16 (1): 133-140. 2008.
    This work, the first book-length study of its topic, is an important contribution to the literature of philosophical logic and philosophy of language, with implications for other branches of philosophy, including philosophy of mathematics. However, five of the book's ten chapters , including many of the author's most original contributions, are devoted to issues about natural language, and lie pretty well outside the scope of this journal, not to mention that of the reviewer's competence. For th…Read more
  •  66
    Axiomatizing the Logic of Comparative Probability
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 51 (1): 119-126. 2010.
    1 Choice conjecture In axiomatizing nonclassical extensions of classical sentential logic one tries to make do, if one can, with adding to classical sentential logic a finite number of axiom schemes of the simplest kind and a finite number of inference rules of the simplest kind. The simplest kind of axiom scheme in effect states of a particular formula P that for any substitution of formulas for atoms the result of its application to P is to count as an axiom. The simplest kind of onepremise in…Read more
  •  65
    Synthetic mechanics
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 13 (4). 1984.
  •  64
    Platonism and Anti-Platonism in Mathematics
    Philosophical Review 110 (1): 79. 2001.
    Mathematics tells us there exist infinitely many prime numbers. Nominalist philosophy, introduced by Goodman and Quine, tells us there exist no numbers at all, and so no prime numbers. Nominalists are aware that the assertion of the existence of prime numbers is warranted by the standards of mathematical science; they simply reject scientific standards of warrant.
  •  61
    Truth and the Absence of Fact
    Philosophical Review 111 (4): 602-604. 2002.
    This volume reprints a dozen of the author’s papers, most with substantial postscripts, and adds one new one. The bulk of the material is on topics in philosophy of language, but there are also two papers on philosophy of mathematics written after the appearance of the author’s collected papers on that subject, and one on epistemology. As to the substance of Field’s contributions, limitations of space preclude doing much more below than indicating the range of issues addressed, and the general o…Read more
  •  60
    There is no prospect of discovering measurable cardinals by radio astronomy, but this does not mean that higher set theory is entirely irrelevant to applied mathematics broadly construed. By way of example, the bearing of some celebrated descriptive-set-theoretic consequences of large cardinals on measurable-selection theory, a body of results originating with a key lemma in von Neumann’s work on the mathematical foundations of quantum theory, and further developed in connection with problems of…Read more