•  51
  •  50
    Vi *-Nietzsche and the re-evaluation of values
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 105 (1): 155-175. 2005.
    This paper offers an account of Nietzsche's re-evaluation of values that seeks to satisfy two desiderata, both important if Nietzsche's project is to stand a chance of success. The first is that Nietzsche's re-evaluations must be capable of being understood as authoritative by those whose values are subject to re-evaluation. The second is that Nietzsche's project must not falsify the values being re-evaluated, by, for example, misrepresenting intrinsic values as instrumental values. Given this, …Read more
  •  49
    Nietzsche, Nature, Nurture
    European Journal of Philosophy 25 (1): 129-143. 2017.
    Nietzsche claims that we are fated to be as we are. He also claims, however, that we can create ourselves. To many commentators these twin commitments have seemed self-contradictory or paradoxical. The argument of this paper, by contrast, is that, despite appearances, there is no paradox here, nor even a tension between Nietzsche's two claims. Instead, when properly interpreted these claims turn out to be intimately related to one another, so that our fatedness emerges as integral to our capacit…Read more
  •  48
    Mr Mew on music
    British Journal of Aesthetics 26 (1): 69-70. 1986.
  •  47
    A Nietzche Round-up
    Philosophical Quarterly 48 (191): 235-242. 1998.
  •  42
    Nietzsche on Language
    Philosophical Topics 33 (2): 1-17. 2005.
  •  38
    Collingwood's commitments: A reply to Hausman and Dilworth
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 56 (4): 396-398. 1998.
  •  37
    Nietzsche on Tragedy: First and Last Thoughts
    The Monist 102 (3): 316-330. 2019.
    Nietzsche is often said to have started out as a Schopenhauerian metaphysician of some kind before leaving Schopenhauer behind him, and, by the end of his sane life, metaphysics too. His first and last thoughts about tragedy, however, sit uneasily with this narrative. The late thoughts are simply too close to the early ones for the story to accommodate them—not for their Schopenhauerianism, but for the strongly metaphysical flavour that they appear to share. The argument of the present paper is …Read more
  •  36
    Congratulations, it's a tragedy: Collingwood's remarks on genre
    British Journal of Aesthetics 42 (1): 52-63. 2002.
    This essay argues that R.G. Collingwood's remarks about genre are implausible, and that they stem, despite their apparent origin in his wider account of art, from his failure to take some of his own most important insights seriously enough. Some possible reasons for that failure are suggested; and it is shown that, once the relevant insights are given their proper weight, Collingwood's account commands the resources from which a plausible story about genre might have been constructed. To this ex…Read more
  •  35
    Presenting some of Nietzsche's most significant thoughts on art and literature, this enthralling account traces the development of his thinking throughout his ...
  •  33
    F.H. Bradley
    Bradley Studies 1 (2): 107-115. 1995.
    The speed with which Bradley became an historical backwater has probably made it easier to think of him as a second-rate philosopher, who was either incompetent or careless, or at any rate uninteresting, and to suppose that his arguments have been refuted as well as rejected. But as far as his metaphysics are concerned this is not the case. His project and his premises are not those of contemporary analytic philosophy, but his arguments are none the less rigorous for that; and attempts to convic…Read more
  •  30
    Still an Error: Relational Theories of Art
    with Alex Neill
    British Journal of Aesthetics 56 (2): 187-189. 2016.
    Aaron Meskin and Simon Fokt have recently taken issue with our 2012 paper, ‘Relational Theories of Art: the History of an Error’. Here we respond to their objections.
  •  28
    II_– _Aaron Ridley
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 71 (1): 163-176. 1997.
  •  27
    This anthology is intended as a core text for courses in aesthetics or philosophy of art. It contains a wealth of readings from both classic and contemporary sources, and aims to present substantial selections from those texts rather than mere "snippets." Readings are organized historically within four broad themes so that students can see how concepts of art have evolved and been debated. Each reading is introduced by the authors, who suggest connections between the reading and others in the an…Read more
  •  24
    On the Musically Possible
    British Journal of Aesthetics 54 (1): 1-14. 2014.
    It seems natural to suppose that Artur Schnabel’s occasionally inaccurate performance of Beethoven’s Hammerklavier would have been even better had it been accurate throughout. In the present paper I defend this supposition against a sceptical argument which purports to show that we have no good reason to believe it. The sceptical argument, which draws on some plausible-seeming thoughts about aesthetic properties, concludes that, because we cannot know whether this or that (as-yet-unachieved) mus…Read more
  •  23
    R.G. Collingwood: a philosophy of art (edited book)
    Phoenix. 1998.
    Many philosophers have been interested in aesthetics, but Collingwood was passionate about art. His theories were never merely theoretical: aesthetics for him was a vivid, vibrant thing, to be experienced immediately in worked paint and in sculptured stones, in poetry and music. Art and life were no dichotomy for Collingwood - for how could you have one without the other? Works of art were created in and for the real world, to be enjoyed by real people, to enchant to enhance. Aaron Ridley's fasc…Read more
  •  22
    II_– _Aaron Ridley
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 71 (1): 163-176. 1997.
  •  21
    Dramatis personae: Nietzsche as cultural physician
    with David Owen
    In Alan D. Schrift (ed.), Why Nietzsche Still? Reflections on Drama, Culture, and Politics, University of California Press. pp. 136-153. 2000.
  •  20
    Discussion of the relations between ethics and aesthetics has tended to focus on issues concerning judgement: for example, philosophers have often asked whether, or to what extent, ethical considerations of one sort or another should inform aesthetic verdicts. Much less discussed, however, have been the relations between these two domains in their practical aspects. In this paper, I try to defuse a cluster of reasons for believing that practical competence in the ethical domain and practical com…Read more
  •  18
    Beginning Bioethics introduces students to the language of philosophical ethics before leading them in Part Two through six major issues in bioethics. The author gives clear explanations of all sides of a given issue and engages with several major contributions to the debate. This book can stand alone, but was written also to accompany the third edition of Bette-Jane Crigger's Cases in Bioethics, providing the philosophical counterpart to cases discussed there by US medical practitioners. Both b…Read more
  •  18
    Nietzsche is one of the most important modern philosophers and his writings on the nature of art are amongst the most influential of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. This_ GuideBook _introduces and assesses: Nietzsche's life and the background to his writings on art the ideas and texts of his works which contribute to art, including _The_ _Birth of Tragedy_, _Human, All Too Human_ and _Thus Spoke Zarathustra_ Nietzsche's continuing importance to philosophy and contemporary thought. This _…Read more
  •  18
    Review: Ancillary Thoughts on an Ancillary Text (review)
    Journal of Nietzsche Studies. forthcoming.
  •  16
    F.H. Bradley
    Bradley Studies 1 (2): 107-115. 1995.
    The speed with which Bradley became an historical backwater has probably made it easier to think of him as a second-rate philosopher, who was either incompetent or careless, or at any rate uninteresting, and to suppose that his arguments have been refuted as well as rejected. But as far as his metaphysics are concerned this is not the case. His project and his premises are not those of contemporary analytic philosophy, but his arguments are none the less rigorous for that; and attempts to convic…Read more
  •  15
    The Deed is Everything offers an engaging new interpretation of Nietzsche as committed to an 'expressivist' conception of agency. Aaron Ridley shows that Nietzsche develops highly distinctive accounts of freedom, morality, and selfhood, with a robust commitment to the value of human excellence in all of its forms.
  •  14
    Acting for Aesthetic Reasons
    Estetika: The European Journal of Aesthetics 54 (1). 2020.
    It seems natural to think that there are aesthetic reasons for action and that an artist must be guided by such reasons as he or she begins work on the canvas or poem or symphony or marble. This latter supposition seems at odds, however, not only with classical inspiration theory but also with the views of one of the last century’s most important philosophers of art, R. G. Collingwood. We propose an account of acting for an aesthetic reason inspired by G. E. M. Anscombe’s Intention, specifically…Read more
  •  12
    Nietzsche on Art and Freedom
    European Journal of Philosophy 15 (2): 204-224. 2007.
    There are passages in Nietzsche that can be read as contributions to the free will/determinism debate. When read in that way, they reveal a fairly amateurish metaphysician with little of real substance or novelty to contribute; and if these readings were apt or perspicuous, it seems to me, they would show that Nietzsche's thoughts about freedom were barely worth pausing over. They would simply confirm the impression—amply bolstered from other quarters—that Nietzsche was not at his best when addr…Read more
  •  12
    Of Mind and Music
    Mind 110 (438): 423-427. 2001.