•  46
  •  45
    Experience and Foundationalism in Audi’s The Architecture of Reason (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67 (1). 2003.
    In The Architecture of Reason, Robert Audi claims that good reasoning always has some foundation in experience. It is not clear, however, precisely what kind of experience is supposed to ground practical reasoning. It is also not clear whether inference is necessary for a belief to be justified, even when the source of the belief is experience without inference. Finally, it is not clear why beliefs based on some kinds of experience would not need to be justified by inference when beliefs based o…Read more
  •  45
    Replies to Copp, Timmons, and Railton (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77 (3): 820-836. 2008.
    No Abstract
  •  44
    Distinct neuronal patterns of positive and negative moral processing in psychopathy
    with Samantha J. Fede, Jana Schaich Borg, Prashanth K. Nyalakanti, Carla L. Hare, Lora M. Cope, Mike Koenigs, Vince D. Calhoun, and Kent A. Kiehl
    Cognitive, Affective, and Behavioral Neuroscience 16 (6). 2016.
    Psychopathy is a disorder characterized by severe and frequent moral violations in multiple domains of life. Numerous studies have shown psychopathy-related limbic brain abnormalities during moral processing; however, these studies only examined negatively valenced moral stimuli. Here, we aimed to replicate prior psychopathy research on negative moral judgments and to extend this work by examining psychopathy-related abnormalities in the processing of controversial moral stimuli and positive mor…Read more
  •  42
    Knobe cites both relevant alternatives and defaults on a continuum to explain how moral judgments influence intuitions about certain apparently non-moral notions. I ask (1) how these two accounts are related, (2) whether they exclude or supplement supposedly competing theories, and (3) how to get positive evidence that people consider relevant alternatives when applying such notions
  •  42
    How to avoid deviance (in logic)
    with Amit Malhotra
    History and Philosophy of Logic 23 (3): 215--36. 2002.
    We show that classical two-valued logic is included in weak extensions of normal three-valued logics and also that normal three-valued logics are best viewed not as deviant logics but instead as strong extensions of classical two-valued logic obtained by adding a modal operator and the right axioms. This article develops a general method for formulating the right axioms to construct a two-valued system with theorems that correspond to all of the logical truths of any normal three-valued logic. T…Read more
  •  41
    For much of the twentieth century, philosophy and science went their separate ways. In moral philosophy, fear of the so-called naturalistic fallacy kept moral philosophers from incorporating developments in biology and psychology. Since the 1990s, however, many philosophers have drawn on recent advances in cognitive psychology, brain science, and evolutionary psychology to inform their work. This collaborative trend is especially strong in moral philosophy, and these three volumes bring together…Read more
  •  40
    Moral Dilemmas and ‘Ought and Ought Not’
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (1): 127-139. 1987.
    Although common sense and literature support the possibility of moral dilemmas, many traditional and contemporary philosophers deny this possibility because of several arguments. Probably the strongest argument against the possibility of moral dilemmas can be called the argument from ought and ought not. Various versions of this argument have been presented by McConnell, Hare, and Conee. Its basic form can be outlined as follows.If any agent is in any moral dilemma, then that agent ought to adop…Read more
  •  40
    The wrongful intentions principle
    Philosophical Papers 20 (1): 11-24. 1991.
    No abstract
  •  37
    Contrastive mental causation
    Synthese 198 (Suppl 3): 861-883. 2019.
    Any theory of mind needs to explain mental causation. Kim’s exclusion argument concludes that non-reductive physicalism cannot meet this challenge. One classic reply is that mental properties capture the causally relevant level of generality, because they are insensitive to physical realization. However, this reply suggests downward exclusion, contrary to physicalism’s assumption of closure. This paper shows how non-reductive physicalists can solve this problem by introducing a contrastive accou…Read more
  •  37
    The Mind, the Brain, and the Law
    with Thomas Nadelhoffer, Dena Gromet, Geoffrey Goodwin, Eddy Nahmias, and Chandra Sripada
    In Thomas A. Nadelhoffer (ed.), The Future of Punishment, Oup Usa. 2013.
  •  36
    Tony honoré, responsibility and fault
    Law and Philosophy 20 (1): 103-106. 2001.
    No Abstract
  •  36
    Classy pyrrhonism
    In Pyrrhonian Skepticism, Oxford University Press. pp. 188--207. 2004.
    This essay invokes a technical framework of contrast classes within which Pyrrhonians can accept knowledge claims that are relativized to specific contrast classes, but avoid all unrelativized knowledge claims and all presuppositions about which contrast classes are really relevant. Pyrrhonians can then assert part of the content of everyday knowledge claims without privileging the everyday perspective or any other perspective. This framework provides a precise way to understand the central clai…Read more
  •  35
    Leading philosophers, psychologists, and neuroscientists address issues of moral responsibility and free will, drawing on new findings from empirical science.
  •  35
    How Stable are Moral Judgments?
    Review of Philosophy and Psychology 14 (4): 1377-1403. 2023.
    Psychologists and philosophers often work hand in hand to investigate many aspects of moral cognition. In this paper, we want to highlight one aspect that to date has been relatively neglected: the stability of moral judgment over time. After explaining why philosophers and psychologists should consider stability and then surveying previous research, we will present the results of an original three-wave longitudinal study. We asked participants to make judgments about the same acts in a series o…Read more
  •  35
    Corrigendum to “Implicit moral evaluations: A multinomial modeling approach” [Cognition 158 (2017) 224–241]
    with C. Daryl Cameron, B. Keith Payne, Julian A. Scheffer, and Michael Inzlicht
    Cognition 173 (C): 138. 2018.
  •  34
    For much of the twentieth century, philosophy and science went their separate ways. In moral philosophy, fear of the so-called naturalistic fallacy kept moral philosophers from incorporating developments in biology and psychology. Since the 1990s, however, many philosophers have drawn on recent advances in cognitive psychology, brain science, and evolutionary psychology to inform their work. This collaborative trend is especially strong in moral philosophy, and these three volumes bring together…Read more
  •  34
    Weak and strong judicial review
    Law and Philosophy 22 (s 3-4): 381-392. 2003.
    No Abstract
  •  34
    Are Proselfs More Deceptive and Hypocritical? Social Image Concerns in Appearing Fair
    with Honghong Tang, Shun Wang, Zilu Liang, Song Su, and Chao Liu
    Frontiers in Psychology 9. 2018.
  •  34
    Making moral principles suit yourself
    with Matthew Stanley, Paul Henne, Laura Niemi, and Felipe De Brigard
    Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 1. 2021.
    Normative ethical theories and religious traditions offer general moral principles for people to follow. These moral principles are typically meant to be fixed and rigid, offering reliable guides for moral judgment and decision-making. In two preregistered studies, we found consistent evidence that agreement with general moral principles shifted depending upon events recently accessed in memory. After recalling their own personal violations of moral principles, participants agreed less strongly …Read more
  •  32
    Contrastive mental causation
    Synthese 198 (Suppl 3): 861-883. 2019.
    Any theory of mind needs to explain mental causation. Kim’s exclusion argument concludes that non-reductive physicalism cannot meet this challenge. One classic reply is that mental properties capture the causally relevant level of generality, because they are insensitive to physical realization. However, this reply suggests downward exclusion, contrary to physicalism’s assumption of closure. This paper shows how non-reductive physicalists can solve this problem by introducing a contrastive accou…Read more
  •  32
    Spreading the Word: Groundings in the Philosophy of Language
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48 (1): 163-166. 1987.
  •  32
    Moral Relativity and Intuitionism
    Philosophical Issues 12 (1): 305-328. 2002.
  •  30
    Free will: philosophers and neuroscientists in conversation (edited book)
    with Uri Maoz
    Oxford University Press. 2022.
    What is free will? Can it exist in a determined universe? How can we determine who, if anyone, possesses it? Philosophers have been debating these questions for millennia. In recent decades neuroscientists have joined the fray with questions of their own. Which neural mechanisms could enable conscious control of action? What are intentional actions? Do contemporary developments in neuroscience rule out free will or, instead, illuminate how it works? Over the past few years, neuroscientists and p…Read more
  •  30
    Adapting a kidney exchange algorithm to align with human values
    with Rachel Freedman, Jana Schaich Borg, John P. Dickerson, and Vincent Conitzer
    Artificial Intelligence 283 (C): 103261. 2020.
  •  30
    20 Years of Moral Epistemology: A Bibliography
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 29 (S1): 217-229. 1991.
  •  30
    Moral experience and justification
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 29 (S1): 89-96. 1991.