•  9
    VI*—Names and Belief
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 81 (1): 93-108. 1981.
    Harold Noonan; VI*—Names and Belief, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 81, Issue 1, 1 June 1981, Pages 93–108, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristotelia.
  •  1
  •  206
    Relative Identity
    Philosophical Investigations 38 (1-2): 52-71. 2015.
    Examples suggest that one and the same A may be different Bs, and hence that there is some sort of incompleteness in the unqualified statement that x and y are the same which needs to be eliminated by answering the question “the same what?” One way to make this more precise is by appeal to Geach's idea that identity is relative. In this paper I evaluate Geach's relative identity thesis
  •  33
    Animalism Versus Lockeanism: A Current Controversy
    Philosophical Quarterly 48 (192): 302-318. 1998.
    My purpose is to explore the possible lines of reply available to a defender of the neo‐Lockean position on personal identity in response to the recently popular ‘animalist’ objection. I compare the animalist objection with an objection made to Locke by Bishop Butler, Thomas Reid and, in our own day, Sydney Shoemaker. I argue that the only possible response available to a defender of Locke against the Butler–Reid–Shoemaker objection is to reject Locke's official definition of a person as a think…Read more
  •  249
    The only X and Y principle
    Analysis 45 (1): 79-83. 1985.
  •  66
    Fregean Thoughts
    Philosophical Quarterly 34 (136): 205-224. 1984.
  •  25
    Can one thing become two?
    Philosophical Studies 33 (3): 203-227. 1978.
    I shall argue that (in a sense to be explained) one thing can become two.
  •  101
    Two Boxing is not the Rational Option
    Ratio 29 (2): 168-183. 2016.
    In the standard Newcomb scenario two-boxing is not the rational act and, in general, in Newcomb-style cases the ‘two-boxing’ choice is not the rational act. Hence any decision theory which recommends two-boxing is unacceptable.
  •  7
    Bob Hale, "Abstract Objects" (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 39 (56): 354. 1989.
  •  14
    Mass Terms: Some Philosophical Problems, edited by F. J. Pelletier (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 30 (120): 259-260. 1980.
  •  88
    Reply to Simons on Coincidence
    Mind 95 (377): 100-104. 1986.
  •  49
    Wiggins on identity
    Mind 85 (340): 559-575. 1976.
  •  389
    Coincidence comes in two varieties – permanent and temporary. Moderate monism is the position that permanent coincidence, but not temporary coincidence, entails identity. Extreme monism is the position that even temporary coincidence entails identity. Pluralists are opponents of monism tout court. The intuitively obvious, commonsensical position is moderate monism. It is therefore important to see if it can be sustained.
  •  33
    Saul Kripke is one of the most important philosophers of the twentieth century. His most celebrated work, Naming and Necessity , makes arguably the most important contribution to the philosophy of language and metaphysics in recent years. Asking fundamental questions – how do names refer to things in the world? Do objects have essential properties? What are natural kind terms and to what do they refer? – he challenges prevailing theories of language and conceptions of metaphysics, especially the…Read more
  •  101
    A Flaw in Kripke’s Modal Argument?
    Philosophia 41 (3): 841-846. 2013.
    The response to Kripke’s modal argument I wish to propose appeals to the distinction between indicative descriptions, i.e., descriptions formed using indicative verb forms, and what I shall call subjunctive descriptions, descriptions formed using non-indicative verb forms used in subjunctive conditionals. The contrast is between ‘the person who is richer than anyone else in the world’ and ‘the person who would have been richer than anyone else in the world’. The response to Kripke’s modal argume…Read more
  •  2
    The self and personal identity
    In Alan Bailey & Dan O'Brien (eds.), The Continuum Companion to Hume, Continuum. pp. 167. 2012.
  •  251
    Identity eliminated
    Analysis 67 (2): 122-127. 2007.
  •  426
    Personal pronoun revisionism (so-called by Olson, E. 2007. What are We? A Study in Personal Ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press) is a response to the problem of the thinking animal on behalf of the neo-Lockean theorist. Many worry about this response. The worry rests on asking the wrong question, namely: how can two thinkers that are so alike differ in this way in their cognitive capacities? This is the wrong question because they don't. The right question is: how can they fail to be the s…Read more
  •  86
    Substance, Identity and Time
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 62 79-100. 1988.
  •  37
    The epistemological problem of relativism – reply to Olson
    Philosophical Studies 104 (3): 323-336. 2001.
  •  9
    Eli Hirsch, "The Concept of Identity" (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 34 (35): 175. 1984.
  •  24
    Persons, animals, and human beings
    In Joseph Keim Campbell, Michael O'Rourke & Harry Silverstein (eds.), Time and Identity, Mit Press. 2010.
    This chapter discusses the suggestion that a psychological approach must be mistaken, because, in fact, the correct account of personal identity is given by the biological approach, according to which we are human beings whose identity over time requires no kind of psychological continuity or connectedness whatsoever. A number of authors support this suggestion, including Paul Snowdon, Peter van Inwagen, and Eric Olson. This also presumes that humans, i.e. members of the species Homo sapiens, ar…Read more
  •  3
    No Title available: New Books (review)
    Philosophy 57 (219): 140-142. 1982.
  •  70
    Supervenience
    Philosophical Quarterly 37 (January): 78-85. 1987.
  •  129
    Methodological solipsism
    Philosophical Studies 40 (September): 269-274. 1981.
  •  129