•  22
    Peirce on Proper Names
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 59 (3): 483-510. 2021.
    ARRAY
  •  22
    Aristotelian Abductions: A Reply to Flórez
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 55 (2): 185. 2019.
    In a brilliant article published in a past issue of the Transactions, Jorge A. Flórez examines Peirce’s theory of the origin of abduction in Aristotle. In the article Flórez makes two substantial points. In the first place, he argues that Peirce’s theory of the origin of abduction in the 25th chapter of the second book of the Prior Analytics is mistaken, because in that chapter Aristotle discusses first-figure syllogisms with a dialectic or contingent minor premise, and not, as Peirce thought, s…Read more
  •  20
    Frege: A fusion of horizontals
    Theoria 89 (5): 690-709. 2023.
    In Die Grundgesetze der Arithmetik (I, §48), Frege introduces his rule of the fusion of horizontals, according to which if an occurrence of the horizontal stroke is followed by another occurrence of the same stroke, either in isolation or “contained” in a propositional connective, the two occurrences can be fused with each other. However, the role of this rule, and of the horizontal sign more generally, is controversial; Michael Dummett notoriously claimed, for instance, that the horizontal is “…Read more
  •  19
    The Sign of Consequence
    The Commens Encyclopedia: The Digital Encyclopedia of Peirce Studies. 2016.
    The “sign of consequence” is a notation for propositional logic that Peirce invented in 1886 and used at least until 1894. It substituted the “copula of inclusion” which he had been using since 1870.
  •  16
    Peirce’s claims that methodeutic “concerns abduction alone” and that “pragmatism contributes to the security of reasoning but hardly to its uberty” are explained. They match as soon as a third claim is taken into account, namely that “pragmatism is the logic of abduction,” not of deduction or induction. Since methodeutic concerns abduction and not deduction or induction, it follows that pragmatism is a maxim of methodeutic. Then, since pragmatism contributes to the security of reasoning but not …Read more
  •  15
    Peirce on Vagueness and Common Sense
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 59 (2): 127-166. 2023.
    Abstract:"Issues of Pragmaticism" (1905) contains the only published version of Peirce's doctrine of "critical common-sensism." One of the claims of that doctrine is that common sense beliefs are invariably vague. In this paper, we seek to explain this claim. We begin by providing a philological reconstruction of the drafts of "Issues of Pragmaticism" and a comparison of Peirce's several, successive expositions of critical common-sensism across those drafts. Then we examine Peirce's theory of va…Read more
  •  15
    _Peirce’s Speculative Grammar: Logic as Semiotics _offers a comprehensive, philologically accurate, and exegetically ambitious developmental account of Peirce’s theory of speculative grammar. The book traces the evolution of Peirce’s grammatical writings from his early research on the classification of arguments in the 1860s up to the complex semiotic taxonomies elaborated in the first decade of the twentieth century. It will be of interest to academic specialists working on Peirce, the history …Read more
  •  15
    In the Posterior Analytics Aristotle contrasts demonstrations with syllogisms through signs. In the Prior Analytics he defines a sign as a demonstrative premise. One is thus led to ask: is a sign a demonstration? This book reconstructs the history of the notion of "demonstration through signs" from roughly the third through to the thirteenth century. It examines the work of Aristotle's Greek, Arabic, and Latin commentators, both within and outside the tradition of the Posterior Analytics.
  •  12
    Peirce, philosophe du langage
    Cahiers Philosophiques 150 (3): 91-110. 2017.
    Cet article soutient que s’il existe une philosophie du langage chez Peirce, il faut la chercher dans sa conception de la grammaire spéculative. Je reconstitue l’évolution de la grammaire spéculative de Peirce dans la période 1894- 1906, et je montre que, tandis que dans les années 1890 la grammaire spéculative est considérée comme une théorie de la proposition, Peirce la conçoit dès 1903 comme une classification générale des signes, incluant une théorie des actes de langage tout à fait pionnièr…Read more
  •  11
    Peirce on Assertion: Preface to the Symposium
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 57 (2): 205-209. 2021.
    ARRAY
  •  7
    Comment
    Sign Systems Studies 43 (4): 433-437. 2015.
  •  7
    Rhemata
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 61 (4): 553-568. 2023.
    The article offers an analysis of Peirce's notion of “rhema.” It examines and explains Peirce's definition of the rhema; it identifies and solves two problems that are direct consequences of the definition. The first problem is that proper names, while classified as rhemata, do not satisfy Peirce's definition of the rhema. The second problem is that Peirce also calls “rhemata” the results of propositional analysis that however do not satisfy his own definition of the rhema. Peirce himself solves…Read more
  •  3
    8 chapters are available open access under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License via link.springer.com.
  • Diagrammatic Representation and Inference. Diagrams 2022 (edited book)
    with V. Giardino, S. Linker, S. Burns, J. M. Boucheix, and P. Viana
    Springer. 2022.
  • Diagrammatic Representation and Inference10th International Conference, Diagrams 2018, Edinburgh, UK, June 18-22, 2018, Proceedings (edited book)
    with Peter Chapman, Gem Stapleton, Amirouche Moktefi, and Sarah Perez-Kriz
    Springer-Verlag. 2018.
  • Habits of Reasoning: On the Grammar and Critics of Logical Habits
    with Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen
    In Myrdene Anderson & Donna West (eds.), Consensus on Peirce’s Concept of Habit, Springer Verlag. 2016.