•  146
    The lure of philosophy in Sydney
    Quadrant 53 (10): 76-79. 2009.
    "Does life have a meaning, and if so what is it? What can I be certain of, and how should I act when I am not certain? Why are the established truths of my tribe better than the primitive superstitions of your tribe? Why should I do as I'm told? Those are questions it is easy to avoid, in the rush to acquire goods and prestige. Even for many of a more serious outlook, they are questions easy to dismiss with excuses like 'it's all a matter of opinion' or 'let's get on with practical matters' or '…Read more
  •  357
    Evidence gained from torture: Wishful thinking, checkability, and extreme circumstances
    Cardozo Journal of International and Comparative Law 17 281-290. 2009.
    "Does torture work?" is a factual rather than ethical or legal question. But legal and ethical discussions of torture should be informed by knowledge of the answer to the factual question of the reliability of torture as an interrogation technique. The question as to whether torture works should be asked before that of its legal admissibility—if it is not useful to interrogators, there is no point considering its legality in court.
  •  346
    A polemical account of Australian philosophy up to 2003, emphasising its unique aspects (such as commitment to realism) and the connections between philosophers' views and their lives. Topics include early idealism, the dominance of John Anderson in Sydney, the Orr case, Catholic scholasticism, Melbourne Wittgensteinianism, philosophy of science, the Sydney disturbances of the 1970s, Francofeminism, environmental philosophy, the philosophy of law and Mabo, ethics and Peter Singer. Realist theori…Read more
  •  301
    Mathematics, core of the past and hope of the future
    In Catherine A. Runcie & David Brooks (eds.), Reclaiming Education: Renewing Schools and Universities in Contemporary Western Society, Edwin H. Lowe Publishing. pp. 149-162. 2018.
    Mathematics has always been a core part of western education, from the medieval quadrivium to the large amount of arithmetic and algebra still compulsory in high schools. It is an essential part. Its commitment to exactitude and to rigid demonstration balances humanist subjects devoted to appreciation and rhetoric as well as giving the lie to postmodernist insinuations that all “truths” are subject to political negotiation. In recent decades, the character of mathematics has changed – or rathe…Read more
  •  667
    Pascal’s wager and the origins of decision theory: decision-making by real decision-makers
    In Paul F. A. Bartha & Lawrence Pasternack (eds.), Pascal’s Wager, Cambridge University Press. pp. 27-44. 2018.
    Pascal’s Wager does not exist in a Platonic world of possible gods, abstract probabilities and arbitrary payoffs. Real decision-makers, such as Pascal’s “man of the world” of 1660, face a range of religious options they take to be serious, with fixed probabilities grounded in their evidence, and with utilities that are fixed quantities in actual minds. The many ingenious objections to the Wager dreamed up by philosophers do not apply in such a real decision matrix. In the situation Pascal addres…Read more
  •  484
    An Argument Against Drug Testing Welfare Recipients
    Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 28 (3): 309-340. 2018.
    Programs of drug testing welfare recipients are increasingly common in US states and have been considered elsewhere. Though often intensely debated, such programs are complicated to evaluate because their aims are ambiguous – aims like saving money may be in tension with aims like referring people to treatment. We assess such programs using a proportionality approach, which requires that for ethical acceptability a practice must be: reasonably likely to meet its aims, sufficiently important in p…Read more
  •  27
    Dynamic context generation for natural language understanding: A multifaceted knowledge approach
    with James Franklin and S. W. K. Chan
    IEEE Transactions on Systems, Man and Cybernetics Part A 33 23-41. 2003.
    We describe a comprehensive framework for text un- derstanding, based on the representation of context. It is designed..
  •  4982
    • It would be a moral disgrace for God (if he existed) to allow the many evils in the world, in the same way it would be for a parent to allow a nursery to be infested with criminals who abused the children. • There is a contradiction in asserting all three of the propositions: God is perfectly good; God is perfectly powerful; evil exists (since if God wanted to remove the evils and could, he would). • The religious believer has no hope of getting away with excuses that evil is not as bad as it …Read more
  •  19
    Is jensenism compatible with christianity?
    Quadrant 48 (12): 30-31. 2004.
    A RECENT BIOGRAPHY of Marcus Loane, evangelical Anglican Archbishop of Sydney in the 1960s, records that as a student at Moore Theological College he would read during lectures to avoid having to listen to the liberal Principal. When you are committed to a closed system of thought, you can't be too careful when it comes to letting ideas in from the outside. But what about the ideas already inside? How does the Sydney Anglican interpretation of Christianity compare to what Jesus said?
  •  290
    The late twentieth century saw two long-term trends in popular thinking about ethics. One was an increase in relativist opinions, with the “generation of the Sixties” spearheading a general libertarianism, an insistence on toleration of diverse moral views (for “Who is to say what is right? – it’s only your opinion.”) The other trend was an increasing insistence on rights – the gross violations of rights in the killing fields of the mid-century prompted immense efforts in defence of the “inalien…Read more
  •  10
    Uncertainty
    Encounter (ABC Radio National) 0-0. 2006.
    Postmodernism is an attitude of suspicion, indeed of unteachable suspicion, in the face of evidence.
  •  78
    Reply to Armstrong on dispositions
    Philosophical Quarterly 38 (150): 86-87. 1988.
    Defends the arguments for the irredicibility of dispositions to categorical properties in "Are dispositions reducible to categorical properties?" (Philosophical Quarterly 36, 1986) against the criticisms of D.M. Armstrong (Philosophical Quarterly 38, 1988).
  •  16
    Australian Philosophy
    Sydney Philosophy Forum. 2010.
    Greek, Latin and Ancient History. Instead, after a good result in mathematics, I decided to pursue that instead. That left me with an extra subject to choose to fill up first year. What was this "Philosophy" on offer? I couldn't understand where there was something in the spectrum of knowledge for philosophy to be about. Biology was about cats, English was about language and literature, mathematics was about numbers (I was not yet philosophically smart enough to realise there was a problem as to…Read more
  •  113
    Book reviews (review)
    Sophia 42 (2): 135-136. 2003.
    Reviews David Stove's collection 'On Enlightenment", attacking Enlightenment shallowness, especially its attack on "superstition" when it had no alternative to offer.
  •  13
    Elected Ignorance (review)
    Quadrant 27 (12): 91-92. 1983.
    Reviews Lewis's account of the low interest Islamic culture has generally shown about other cultures, and suggests that Islamic openness caused by military weakness may be imitated by the Soviet Union.
  •  18
    publication and Now, it may well be that some wet-behind-the-ears bishops with little understanding of economics do use the term Governments relies on the “social justice” to give a colour of moral dignity to views that are a touch socialist. But what was missing in Abbott’s cannot pick winners generosity of its..
  •  77
    Symbolic connectionism in natural language disambiguation
    with James Franklin and S. W. K. Chan
    IEEE Transactions on Neural Networks 9 739-755. 1998.
    Uses connectionism (neural networks) to extract the "gist" of a story in order to represent a context going forward for the disambiguation of incoming words as a text is processed.
  •  32
    Scepticism′s Health Buoyant
    Philosophy 69 (270). 1994.
    Replies to O. Hanfling, ‘Healthy scepticism?’, Philosophy 68 (1993), 91-3, which criticized J. Franklin, ‘Healthy scepticism’, Philosophy 66 (1991), 305-324. The symmetry argument for scepticism is defended (that there is no reason to prefer the realist alternative to sceptical ones).
  •  52
    Natural sciences as textual interpretation: The hermeneutics of the natural sign
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 44 (4): 509-520. 1984.
    There are close parallels between perception (the interpretation of sensory experience as representing physical objects) and hermeneutics (the interpretation of signs as having meaning). Perceptual illusions corresponds to ambiguities in texts; naive realism corresponds to fundamentalism; the scientist's reinterpretation of the "manifest image" to the global/local interplay of the "hermeneutic circle" in the interpretation of large texts.
  •  55
    Assessment of strategies for evaluating extreme risks
    with James Franklin and Scott Sisson
    Australian Centre of Excellence for Risk Analysis Reports. 2007.
    The report begins by outlining several case studies with varying levels of data, examining the role for extreme event risk analysis. The case studies include BA’s analysis of fire blight and New Zealand apples, bank operational risk and several technical failures. The report then surveys recent developments in methods relevant to evaluating extreme risks and evaluates their properties. These include methods for fraud detection in banks, formal extreme value theory, Bayesian approaches, qualitati…Read more
  •  43
    Talk about ethics involves a great number of different sorts of concepts – rules, virtues, values, outcomes, rights, etc … Ethics is about all those things, but it is not fundamentally about them. Let’s review them with a view to seeing why they are not basic.
  •  416
    Science by Conceptual Analysis
    Studia Neoaristotelica 9 (1): 3-24. 2012.
    The late scholastics, from the fourteenth to the seventeenth centuries, contributed to many fields of knowledge other than philosophy. They developed a method of conceptual analysis that was very productive in those disciplines in which theory is relatively more important than empirical results. That includes mathematics, where the scholastics developed the analysis of continuous motion, which fed into the calculus, and the theory of risk and probability. The method came to the fore especially i…Read more
  •  137
    Powerful, technically complex international compliance regimes have developed recently in certain professions that deal with risk: banking (the Basel II regime), accountancy (IFRS) and the actuarial profession. The need to deal with major risks has acted as a strong driver of international co-operation to create enforceable international semilegal systems, as happened earlier in such fields as international health regulations. This regulation in technical fields contrasts with the failure of an in…Read more
  •  26
    Is philosophy irrelevant to science?
    Philosopher's Zone (ABC Radio National) 0-0. 2009.
    Scientists get on with the job – they do stuff with test tubes or with computers – but can philosophers help them? Do they need help and, if so, do they think they need help? This week, we examine what philosophers of science talk about and what effect it might have on what scientists actually do.
  •  238
    Thomas Kuhn's irrationalism
    New Criterion 18 (10): 29-34. 2000.
    Criticizes the irrationalist and social constructionist tendencies in Kuhn's Structure of Scientific Revolutions.
  •  434
    Aristotle on Species Variation
    Philosophy 61 (236). 1986.
    Explains Aristotle's views on the possibility of continuous variation between biological species. While the Porphyrean/Linnean classification of species by a tree suggests species are distributed discretely, Aristotle admitted continuous variation between species among lower life forms.
  •  46
    Species in Aristotle
    Philosophy 64 (247). 1989.
    Reply to H. Granger, Aristotle and the finitude of natural kinds, Philosophy 62 (1987), 523-26, which discussed J. Franklin, Aristotle on species variation, Philosophy 61 (1986), 245-52.
  •  153
    The Sokal hoax
    The Philosopher 1 (4): 21-24. 1996.
    Describes the Sokal hoax and defends it against attacks by postmodernists.
  •  65
    The renaissance myth
    Quadrant 26 (11): 51-60. 1982.
    THE HISTORY OF IDEAS is full of more tall stories than most other departments of history. Here are three which manage to combine initial implausibility with impregnability to refutation: that in the Middle Ages it was believed that the world was flat; that medieval philosophers debated as to how many angels could dance on the head of a pin; that Galileo revolutionised physics by dropping weights from the Leaning Tower of Pisa. None of these stories is true, and no competent historian has asserte…Read more