•  14
    We spend a lot of time arguing about how schools might be improved. But we rarely take a step back to ask what we as a society should be looking for from education—what exactly should those who make decisions be trying to achieve? In Educational Goods, two philosophers and two social scientists address this very question. They begin by broadening the language for talking about educational policy: “educational goods” are the knowledge, skills, and attitudes that children develop for their own ben…Read more
  •  13
    What's Wrong with Tuition‐Free Four‐Year Public College?
    with Kailey Mullane
    Educational Theory 73 (6): 833-859. 2024.
    Advocates of tuition-free four-year public college make the argument for it too easy by asserting that it would be paid for out of taxes on the wealthy. Other uses of the revenues are possible. In this paper, Harry Brighouse and Kailey Mullane establish two criteria for comparing different uses of the revenues: the first criterion is, will the policy increase the overall level of educational goods?, and the second is, will the policy reduce inequalities of educational goods? Here, Brighouse and …Read more
  •  12
    Against Nationalism
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 26 (sup1): 365-405. 1997.
  •  11
    Most of the estimated 855 million people in the world (one sixth of the population) without access to schooling are women and girls. Two thirds of the 110 million school age children not in school are girls (UNGEI, 2002). This injustice has been a focus of attempts at coordinated international policy interventions since the 1990s, sometimes loosely referred to as the Education for All (EFA) movement. The first of the millennium development targets - gender equity in education - is supposed to be…Read more
  •  11
    Perpetuating the discipline of philosophy is not the main educational responsibility of philosophers. Instead, it is to equip students with those distinctively philosophical intellectual resources that will serve students in serving the public good through participation in the economy (broadly conceived) and democratic life. Given this responsibility philosophers, individually and collectively, have a duty to take teaching and learning more seriously than they do. The paper offers some confident…Read more
  •  10
    Debating Education puts two leading scholars in conversation with each other on the subject of education-specifically, what role, if any, markets should play in policy reform. The authors focus on the nature, function, and legitimate scope of voluntary exchange as a form of social relation, and how education raises concerns that are not at issue when it comes to trading relationships between consenting adults.
  •  10
    On Alex Callinicos's Equality (review)
    with Erik Olin Wright
    Historical Materialism 10 (1): 193-222. 2002.
  •  10
    Is There a Neutral Justification for Liberalism?†
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 77 (3): 193-215. 2017.
    Neutralist defenses of liberalism fail because they cannot account for essential features of an acceptable liberal theory: a firm guarantee for a sphere of individual liberty, an account of our interest in being able to revise our moral commitments, a wide range of applicability, and the possibility of legitimate government in the face of rejection by unreasonable citizens. A liberalism based on the value of autonomy can address the problems which motivate neutralists, while succeeding in provid…Read more
  •  9
    Education, Justice, Ideal Theory, and Non-ideal Theory
    Philosophy of Education 70 15-20. 2014.
  •  9
    A Modest Defence of School Choice
    Journal of Philosophy of Education 36 (4): 653-659. 2002.
    This is a response to Samara Foster’s engaging critique of my book School Choice and Social Justice. In this response to her criticisms I clarify and try to correct some apparent misunderstandings of the book, but also take the opportunity to pose again a challenge to opponents of choice which neither she, nor other of my critics, has taken up.
  •  9
    Brill Online Books and Journals
    with Ellen Meiksins Wood, Ray Kiely, Enzo Traverso, Patrick Murray, Erik Olin Wright, Paresh Chattopadhyay, Chris Arthur, Alex Law, and Thomas M. Jeannot
    Historical Materialism 1 (1). 1997.
  •  9
    This chapter contains sections titled: Objections.
  •  8
    Transitional and Utopian Market Socialism
    Politics and Society 22 (4): 569-584. 1994.
  •  6
    Is There Any Such Thing as Political Liberalism?
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 75 (3-4): 318-332. 2017.
  •  6
    Educational Justice and Socio‐Economic Segregation in Schools
    In Mark Halstead & Graham Haydon (eds.), The Common School and the Comprehensive Ideal, Wiley‐blackwell. 2008-10-10.
    This chapter contains sections titled: I Justice in Education II The Comprehensive Ideal III Socioeconomic Segregation and Educational Injustice IV Liberty, Family Values and Justice V Justice without Structural Reform? VI Justice without De‐Segregation? VII Concluding Comment Notes References.
  •  5
    Education: Not a Real Utopian Design
    Politics and Society 42 (1): 51-72. 2014.
    This paper identifies four criteria, all of which an ideal real utopian proposal would meet. We argue for a moderate skepticism that it is possible to give a real utopian proposal to guide the design of education for a society that meets these criteria; both for the practical reason that what happens in schools depends on the background environment within which they operate, and for the principled reason that when educating children we should attend to their individual future well-being in ways …Read more
  •  4
    Egalitarian Liberals and School Choice
    Politics and Society 24 (4): 457-486. 1996.
  •  4
    Funding Religious Schools
    Philosophy of Education 60 72-75. 2004.
  •  3
    No Title available: REVIEWS
    Economics and Philosophy 10 (1): 127-133. 1994.
  •  1
    Citizenship
    In Catriona McKinnon (ed.), Issues in Political Theory, Oxford University Press. 2008.
  • Andrée-Anne Cormier and Harry Brighouse explore the question of whether there are good reasons for schools to try and produce citizens disposed to use, and practiced in, civil discourse and behavior, and if so, what this implies for schools. First, the authors propose an account of the value (and disvalue) of civility, drawing on Cheshire Calhoun’s conception. They argue that civility is good in many circumstances, but not always. In some circumstances, it is neither beneficial nor morally requi…Read more
  • Justice
    Philosophical Quarterly 55 (221): 688-690. 2005.
  • Book Review (review)
    Economics and Philosophy 10 (1): 127-133. 1994.
  • In my contribution today I want to talk about the place of private schooling in a society devoted to educational justice. I should say at the outset that although there are no principled reasons for opposing private schooling - certainly none in favour of the idea that the state should have a monopoly on provision - I do not share the enthusiasm that many of today's speakers have shown for private schools. Whether or not they are consistent with a just distribution of schooling is a highly conti…Read more