• Reply to David Charles
    Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 207-214. 1988.
  •  98
    The essays in this volume were written to celebrate the sixtieth birthday of G. E. L. Owen, who by his essays and seminars on ancient Greek philosophy has made a contribution to its study that is second to none. The authors, from both sides of the Atlantic, include not only scholars whose main research interests lie in Greek philosophy, but others best known for their work in general philosophy. All are pupils or younger colleagues of Professor Owen who are indebted to his practice of philosophi…Read more
  •  50
    The philosophers of the Hellenistic schools in ancient Greece and Rome (Epicureans, Stoics, Sceptics, Academics, Cyrenaics) made important contributions to the philosophy of mind and the philosophy of psychology. This volume, which contains the proceedings of the Fifth Symposium Hellenisticum, describes and analyses their contributions on issues such as: the nature of perception, imagination and belief; the nature of the passions and their role in action; the relationship between mind and body; …Read more
  •  336
    Transitional Anger
    Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1 (1): 41--56. 2015.
    ABSTRACT ABSTRACT: A close philosophical analysis of the emotion of anger will show that it is normatively irrational: in some cases, based on futile magical thinking, in others, based on defective values
  •  127
    Virtue Ethics: The Misleading Category
    Areté. Revista de Filosofía 11 (1): 533-571. 1999.
    La ética de la virtud es frecuentemente considerada una categoría singular de la teoría ética, y una rival del kantismo y del utilitarismo. Considero que es un error, puesto que tanto kantianos como utilitaristas pueden tener, y tienen, un interés en las virtudes y en la formación del carácter. Mas, aun si focalizamos el grupo de teóricos de la ética, comúnmente llamados "teóricos de la virtud", porque rechazan la dirección tanto del kantismo como del utilitarismo y se inspiran en la ética grieg…Read more
  •  902
    Compassion: The Basic Social Emotion
    Social Philosophy and Policy 13 (1): 27. 1996.
    Philoctetes was a good man and a good soldier. When he was on his way to Troy to fight alongside the Greeks, he had a terrible misfortune. By sheer accident he trespassed in a sacred precinct on the island of Lemnos. As punishment he was bitten on the foot by the serpent who guarded the shrine. His foot began to ooze with foul-smelling pus, and the pain made him cry out curses that spoiled the other soldiers' religious observances. They therefore left him alone on the island, a lame man with no …Read more
  • Applying the Lessons of Ancient Greece Martha C. Nussbaum
    with Bill D. Moyers, Public Affairs Television, and Films for the Humanities
    Films for the Humanities & Sciences. 1989.
  •  157
    This volume brings together Nussbaum's published papers on the relationship between literature and philosophy, especially moral philosophy. The papers, many of them previously inaccessible to non-specialist readers, explore such fundamental issues as the relationship between style and content in the exploration of ethical issues; the nature of ethical attention and ethical knowledge and their relationship to written forms and styles; and the role of the emotions in deliberation and self-knowledg…Read more
  •  257
    Wuthering heights: The romantic ascent
    Philosophy and Literature 20 (2): 362-382. 1996.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Wuthering Heights: The Romantic AscentMartha NussbaumI“If I were in heaven, Nelly,” she said, “I should be extremely miserable.”“I dreamt, once, that I was there.... [H]eaven did not seem to be my home; and I broke my heart with weeping to come back to earth; and the angels were so angry that they flung me out, into the middle of the heath on the top of Wuthering Heights, where I woke sobbing for joy.” 1Cathy’s soul cannot live in th…Read more
  •  212
    Radical evil in the Lockean state: The neglect of the political emotions
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 3 (2): 159-178. 2006.
    All modern liberal democracies have strong reasons to support an idea of toleration, understood as involving respect, not only grudging acceptance, and to extend it to all religious and secular doctrines, limiting only conduct that violates the rights of other citizens. There is no modern democracy, however, in which toleration of this sort is a stable achievement. Why is toleration, attractive in principle, so difficult to achieve? The normative case for toleration was well articulated by John …Read more
  •  2
    Internal criticism and Indian rationalist traditions
    World Institute for Development Economics Research of the United Nations University. 1987.
  •  317
    Exactly and responsibly: A defense of ethical criticism
    Philosophy and Literature 22 (2): 343-365. 1998.
  •  1
    Linker Aristotelismus. Rez. zu:; Gerechtigkeit oder Das gute Leben
    with J. Schenuit
    Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 47 (6): 1063-1068. 1999.
  •  187
    This book is a study of ancient views about 'moral luck'. It examines the fundamental ethical problem that many of the valued constituents of a well-lived life are vulnerable to factors outside a person's control, and asks how this affects our appraisal of persons and their lives. The Greeks made a profound contribution to these questions, yet neither the problems nor the Greek views of them have received the attention they deserve. This book thus recovers a central dimension of Greek thought an…Read more
  •  15
    Nature, function, and capability: Aristotle on political distribution
    World Institute for Development Economics Research of the United Nations University. 1987.
  •  90
    Hiding from humanity: Replies to Charlton, Haldane, Archard, and Brooks
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 25 (4): 335-349. 2008.
    No Abstract
  •  84
    Skeptic purgatives: Therapeutic arguments in ancient skepticism
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 29 (4): 521-557. 1991.