Providence, Rhode Island, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
Metaphysics
Philosophy of Mind
  •  119
    States of Affairs, Events, and Propositions
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 7 147-162. 1979.
    States of affairs constitute a basic ontological category in Chisholm's metaphysical system, and yield events and propositions as subclasses. Qua events, they enter into causal relations, and qua propositions, they are objects of our intentional attitudes. This paper expounds and critically examines Chisholm's conception of a state of affairs and his constructions of events and propositions. Various difficulties with some of Chisholm's definitions and procedures are pointed out and discussed. Th…Read more
  •  109
    It was about half a century ago that the mind–body problem, which like much else in serious metaphysics had been moribund for several decades, was resurrected as a mainstream philosophical problem. The first impetus came from Gilbert Ryle's The Concept of Mind , published in 1948, and Wittgenstein's well-known, if not well-understood, reflections on the nature of mentality and mental language, especially in his Philosophical Investigations which appeared in 1953. The primary concerns of Ryle and…Read more
  •  100
    Possible Worlds and Annstrong’s Combinatorialism
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16 (4): 595-612. 1986.
    At the outset of his instructive and thought-provoking paper, ‘The Nature of Possibility,’ Professor David Armstrong gives a succinct description, in itself almost complete, of his ‘combinatorial theory’ of possibility. He says: ‘Such a view traces the very idea of possibility to the idea of the combinations - allthe combinations which respect certain simple form- of given, actual elements’. We can perhaps start a bit further back than this. In explaining the idea of a ‘possible world,’ some phi…Read more
  •  99
    Laws, Causation, and Explanation in the Special Sciences
    History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 27 (3/4). 2005.
    There is the general philosophical question concerning the relationship between physics, which is often taken to be our fundamental and all-encompassing science, on one hand and the special sciences, such as biology and psychology, each of which deals with phenomena in some specially restricted domain, on the other. This paper deals with a narrower question: Are there laws in the special sciences, laws like those we find, or expect to find, in basic physics? Three arguments that are intended to …Read more
  •  98
    Review of E xplanation and Understanding (review)
    Philosophical Review 82 (3): 380-388. 1973.
  •  92
    Materialism and the criteria of the mental
    Synthese 22 (3-4): 323-345. 1971.
    Peer Reviewed.
  •  83
    On the logical conditions of deductive explanation
    Philosophy of Science 30 (3): 286-291. 1963.
    Hempel and Oppenheim have stated in Part III of their paper “Studies in the Logic of Explanation” [2] a set of conditions for deductive explanation. However, their analysis has come under damaging systematic criticisms in a recent paper by Eberle, Kaplan and Montague [1], The principal aim of the present paper is to review the Hempel-Oppenheim analysis and propose a strengthened version of it that avoids the recent criticisms.
  •  83
    Horgan’s naturalistic metaphysics of mind
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 63 (1): 27-52. 2002.
    Terry Horgan has made impressive and highly important contributions to numerous fields of philosophy ? metaphysics, philosophy of mind and psychology, philosophy of language, philosophy of science, and value theory, to mention the most prominent ones. What gives Horgan's work a powerful and clarifying unity is his deep and unflagging commitment to philosophical naturalism. In fact, Horgan himself has often invoked naturalism to motivate his positions and arguments on a number of philosophical is…Read more
  •  75
    What Could Pair a Nonphysical Soul to a Physical Body?
    In Keith Augustine & Michael Martin (eds.), The Myth of an Afterlife: The Case against Life After Death, Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 335-347. 2015.
    This paper argues that since nonphysical souls lack a position in space, they cannot have the pairing relations that would allow them to interact with physical bodies. For example, if two rifles (A and B) are fired at the same time, and consequently Andy and Buddy are killed, we can only say that rifle A killed Andy while rifle B killed Buddy, rather than the other way around, if there are appropriate spatial relations (such as distance and orientation) that pair Andy’s death to A’s firing, and …Read more
  •  74
    Inference, explanation, and prediction
    Journal of Philosophy 61 (12): 360-368. 1964.
  •  74
    The Mind–Body Problem after Fifty Years
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 43 3-21. 1998.
    It was about half a century ago that the mind–body problem, which like much else in serious metaphysics had been moribund for several decades, was resurrected as a mainstream philosophical problem. The first impetus came from Gilbert Ryle'sThe Concept of Mind, published in 1948, and Wittgenstein's well-known, if not well-understood, reflections on the nature of mentality and mental language, especially in hisPhilosophical Investigationswhich appeared in 1953. The primary concerns of Ryle and Wit…Read more
  •  66
  •  64
    Supervenience for multiple domains
    Philosophical Topics 16 (1): 129-50. 1988.
  •  63
    Supervenient properties and micro-based concepts: A reply to Noordhof
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99 (1): 115-118. 1999.
    Jaegwon Kim; Supervenient Properties and Micro-Based Properties: A reply to Noordhof, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 99, Issue 1, 1 June 1999
  •  62
    Responses
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (3). 2002.
    Jackson says that the form of physicalism that I recommend, with certain emendations he believes are necessary, turns out to be none other than the “Australian” type-type identity theory of J.J.C. Smart and others. About this, too, I have no serious disagreement, although Jackson’s claim appears to depend, at least in part, on a certain chosen reading of the texts involved. In fact, one point of similarity may be worth noting. As I take it, one special feature of the “Australian” type identity t…Read more
  •  58
    Multiple Realization and the Metaphysics of Reduction
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (1): 1-26. 1992.
  •  53
    Supervenience, emergence, and realization in the philosophy of mind
    In P. Machamer & M. Carrier (eds.), Mindscapes: Philosophy, Science, and the Mind, Pittsburgh University Press and Universtaetsverlag Konstanz. pp. 271. 1997.
  •  50
    Perceiving numbers and numerical relations
    Noûs 16 (1): 93-94. 1982.
  •  50
    Mind in a Physical World
    Noûs 35 (2): 304-316. 2001.