Cambridge, United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland
  •  54
    Williams, Smith, and the Peculiarity of Piacularity
    Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1 (2): 217--232. 2015.
  •  4
    Replies
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (1): 164-176. 2002.
    Dreier’s sympathy with expressivism is welcome, and yet he comes upon an ‘uncomfortable surprise’, in a circularity or regress that he detects in my attempt to place ethical commitments in a natural world. The circularity is that the expressivist analysis of what is going on, when we invoke norms, identifies particular states of mind: valuings, or acceptance of norms, or complexes of attitude. But states of mind are themselves normatively tainted. Hence: ‘the kernel of expressivist analysis invo…Read more
  •  238
    (2000). Critical notice of Frank Jackson, from metaphysics to ethics: A defence of conceptual analysis. Australasian Journal of Philosophy: Vol. 78, No. 1, pp. 119-124. doi: 10.1080/00048400012349401
  •  88
    Success Semantics
    In Hallvard Lillehammer & D. H. Mellor (eds.), Ramsey's Legacy, Oxford University Press. 2005.
  •  117
    Interview - Simon Blackburn
    The Philosophers' Magazine 40 (40): 38-39. 2008.
    Cambridge professor Simon Blackburn is best known to the general public as the author of several books of popular philosophy such as  ink, Being Good andTruth: a Guide for the Perplexed. Academic philosophers also know him as the author of one of the most important books of contemporary moral philosophy, Ruling Passions, and as a former editor of the leading journal Mind.
  • Wittgenstein and Minimalism
    In B. Garrett & K. Mulligan (eds.), Themes From Wittgenstein, Anu Working Papers in Philosophy 4. pp. 1--14. 1993.
  •  15
    Professor whatever
    Disputatio 1 (8): 1-12. 2000.
  •  91
    The idea behind expressivism as a philosophy of ethics faces a number of different challenges, and has a number of different choices to make as it tries to meet them. Perhaps the first is to specify what is the primitive of the theory, which will be something that is expressed, and is usually identified as a state of mind. Later in this paper, I shall suggest caution about this, but for the moment we can go along with it. Emotion was one suggestion, prescriptions are another, desires of various …Read more
  •  79
    16 How to be an Ethical Antirealist
    In Paul K. Moser & J. D. Trout (eds.), Contemporary Materialism: A Reader, Routledge. pp. 357. 1995.
  •  98
    Précis of ruling passions (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (1). 2002.
    Ruling Passions is about human nature. It is an invitation to see human nature a certain way. It defends this way of looking at ourselves against competitors, including rational choice theory, modern Kantianism, various applications of evolutionary psychology, views that enchant our natures, and those that disenchant them in the direction of relativism or nihilism. It is a story centred upon a view of human ethical nature, which it places amongst other facets of human nature, as just one of the …Read more
  •  89
  •  302
    Being Good: A Short Introduction to Ethics
    Oxford University Press. 2001.
    This is a very short introduction to ethics. It divides into three parts: first, introducing and discussing reasons for skepticism about ethics; second introducing themes of birth, death, happiness, desire and freedom to show how deeply our lives are interwoven with ethics; third, introducing attempts to found ethics, due to Aristotle, Kant, and the contractarian tradition.
  •  418
    Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning
    Oxford University Press UK. 1998.
    Simon Blackburn puts forward a compelling original philosophy of human motivation and morality. He maintains that we cannot get clear about ethics until we get clear about human nature. So these are the sorts of questions he addresses: Why do we behave as we do? Can we improve? Is our ethics at war with our passions, or is it an upshot of those passions? Blackburn seeks the answers in an exploration of guilt, shame, disgust, and other moral emotions; he draws also on game theory and cognitive sc…Read more
  •  17
    How can we tell whether a commitment has a truth condition
    In Charles Travis (ed.), Meaning and interpretation, Blackwell. pp. 201--232. 1986.
  •  8
    The landscapes of pragmatism
    Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 28 (3): 31-48. 2009.
  •  107
    Normativity à la mode
    The Journal of Ethics 5 (2): 139-153. 2001.
    This paper sets out to raise questions about the metaphor of the spaceof reasons. It argues that a proper appreciation of Wittgensteinundermines the metaphysical or dualistic way of taking the metaphor thatis supposed to prevent the naturalization of reason.
  •  29
    Fiction and Conviction
    Philosophical Papers 32 (3): 243-260. 2003.
    Abstract In this piece I take issue with Bernard Williams's interpretation of Herodotus as lacking something of our conception of time. I claim that there is nothing so unusual in the interleaving of myth or fiction and history that Williams finds in Herodotus. I also reflect on the difficulty of separating acceptance of truth from acceptance of myth, metaphor, and model, not only in history but also in science
  •  301
  •  79
    Some years ago, without realizing what it might mean, I accepted a dinner invitation from a Jewish colleague for dinner on Friday night. I should say that my colleague had never appeared particularly orthodox, and he would have known that I am an atheist. However, in the course of the meal, some kind of observance was put in train, and it turned out I was expected to play along—put on a hat, or some such. I demurred, saying that I felt uncomfortable doing something that might be the expression o…Read more
  •  4
    Escaping the straitjacket
    The Philosophers' Magazine 38 42-43. 2007.
  •  554
    Think: a compelling introduction to philosophy
    Oxford University Press. 1999.
    Here at last is a coherent, unintimidating introduction to the challenging and fascinating landscape of Western philosophy. Written expressly for "anyone who believes there are big questions out there, but does not know how to approach them," Think provides a sound framework for exploring the most basic themes of philosophy, and for understanding how major philosophers have tackled the questions that have pressed themselves most forcefully on human consciousness. Simon Blackburn, author of the b…Read more
  •  76
    Making ends meet
    Philosophical Books 27 (4): 193-203. 1986.
    Williams’s arguments against the morality system are given canonical form in Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, chapter 10, where he undertakes to describe this particular form of ethical thinking and explain “why we would be better off without it”.
  •  3
    Dilemmas: Dithering, Plumping, and Grief
    In H. E. Mason (ed.), Moral Dilemmas and Moral Theory, Oxford University Press. pp. 127. 1996.
  •  1
    Spreading the world
    Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 176 (3): 385-387. 1986.
  •  59
    Julius Caesar and George Berkeley Play Leapfrog
    In Cynthia Macdonald & Graham Macdonald (eds.), Mcdowell and His Critics, Blackwell. pp. 6--203. 2006.
  •  45
    What’s it all about?
    The Philosophers' Magazine 27 20-21. 2004.
  •  22
    Reviews (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 22 (2): 371-373. 1971.
  •  9
    Como é a Filosofia Analítica Possível?
    Disputatio 1 (4): 2-24. 1998.