•  76
    E. J. Lowe; Reply to ramachandran on conditionals and transitivity, Analysis, Volume 52, Issue 2, 1 April 1992, Pages 77–80, https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/52.2.
  •  76
  •  75
    Some formal ontological relations
    Dialectica 58 (3). 2004.
    Some formal ontological relations are identified, in the context of an account of ontological categorization. It is argued that neither formal ontological relations nor ontological categories should themselves be regarded as elements of being, but that this does not undermine the claim of formal ontology to be a purely objective science. It is also argued that some formal ontological relations, like some ontological categories, are more basic than others. A four‐category ontology is proposed, in…Read more
  •  75
    Substance causation, powers, and human agency
    In E. J. Lowe, S. Gibb & R. D. Ingthorsson (eds.), Mental Causation and Ontology, Oxford Up. pp. 153--172. 2013.
    Introduction , Sophie Gibb 1. Mental Causation , John Heil 2. Physical Realization without Preemption , Sydney Shoemaker 3. Mental Causation in the Physical World , Peter Menzies 4. Mental Causation: Ontology and Patterns of Variation , Paul Noordhof 5. Causation is Macroscopic but not Irreducible , David Papineau 6. Substance Causation, Powers, and Human Agency , E. J. Lowe 7. Agent Causation in a Neo-Aristotelian Metaphysics , Jonathan D. Jacobs and Timothy O’Connor 8. Mental Causation and Dou…Read more
  •  74
    Powerful Particulars: Review Essay on John Heil’s From an Ontological Point of View (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (2): 466--479. 2006.
    John Heil’s new book is remarkable in many ways. In a concise, lucid and accessible manner, it develops a complete system of ontology with many strikingly original features and then applies that ontology to fundamental issues in the philosophy of mind, with illuminating results. Although Heil acknowledges his intellectual debts to C. B. Martin, he is unduly modest about his own contribution to the development and application of this novel metaphysical system. A full examination of the position t…Read more
  •  70
    Substance and Selfhood
    Philosophy 66 (255): 81-99. 1991.
    How could the self be a substance? There are various ways in which it could be, some familiar from the history of philosophy. I shall be rejecting these more familiar substantivalist approaches, but also the non-substantival theories traditionally opposed to them. I believe that the self is indeed a substance—in fact, that it is a simple or noncomposite substance—and, perhaps more remarkably still, that selves are, in a sense, self-creating substances. Of course, if one thinks of the notion of s…Read more
  •  69
    What Is the 'Problem of Induction'?
    Philosophy 62 (241). 1987.
    This paper falls into three parts. In the first I retrace the steps which, have led many to consider that there is a ‘problem of induction’ which may have only a sceptical solution. In the second I explain why I think we cannot rest content with such a solution. In the third I try to show how a new approach to certain key concepts in the philosophy of science—in particular the concept of natural law —may help towards a non-sceptical resolution of the problem
  •  69
    The topology of visual appearance
    Erkenntnis 25 (3): 271-274. 1986.
  •  68
    Laws, Dispositions and Sortal Logic
    American Philosophical Quarterly 19 (1). 1982.
  •  67
    Psycho-Physical Dualism Today: An Interdisciplinary Approach
    with Friedrich Beck, Carl Johnson, Franz von Kutschera, Uwe Meixner, David S. Oderberg, Ian J. Thompson, and Henry Wellman
    Lexington Books. 2008.
    Until quite recently, mind-body dualism has been regarded with deep suspicion by both philosophers and scientists. This has largely been due to the widespread identification of dualism in general with one particular version of it: the interactionist substance dualism of Réné Descartes. This traditional form of dualism has, ever since its first formulation in the seventeenth century, attracted numerous philosophical objections and is now almost universally rejected in scientific circles as empiri…Read more
  •  67
    Le réalisme métaphysique est la conception suivant laquelle la plupart des objets qui peuplent le monde existent indépendamment de notre pensée et possèdent une nature indépendante de la manière dont nous pouvons éventuellement la concevoir. A mon sens cette position engage à admettre une forme robuste d'essentialisme. Beaucoup des formes modernes de l'anti-réalisme tirent leurs origines d'une forme de conceptualisme, suivant laquelle toutes les vérités que nous puissions connaître au sujet des …Read more
  •  66
    The Metaphysics of Abstract Objects
    Journal of Philosophy 92 (10): 509-524. 1995.
  •  66
    How Not to Think of Powers
    The Monist 94 (1): 19-33. 2011.
  •  66
    Review: Powers: A study in metaphysics (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55 (4): 817-822. 2004.
  •  66
    Forms of Thought: A Study in Philosophical Logic
    Cambridge University Press. 2013.
    Forms of thought are involved whenever we name, describe, or identify things, and whenever we distinguish between what is, might be, or must be the case. It appears to be a distinctive feature of human thought that we can have modal thoughts, about what might be possible or necessary, and conditional thoughts, about what would or might be the case if something else were the case. Even the simplest thoughts are structured like sentences, containing referential and predicative elements, and studyi…Read more
  •  63
    Self, Reference and Self-Reference
    Philosophy 68 (263): 15-33. 1993.
    I favour an analysis of selfhood which ties it to the possession of certain kinds of first-person knowledge, in particular de re knowledge of the identity of one's own conscious thoughts and experiences. My defence of this analysis will lead me to explore the nature of demonstrative reference to one's own conscious thoughts and experiences. Such reference is typically ‘direct’, in contrast to demonstrative reference to all physical objects, apart from those that are parts of one's own body in wh…Read more
  •  61
    Primitive Substances
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (3). 1994.
  •  61
    E. J. Lowe; One-level versus two-level identity criteria, Analysis, Volume 51, Issue 4, 1 October 1991, Pages 192–194, https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/51.4.192.
  •  61
    E. J. Lowe; Wright versus Lewis on the transitivity of counterfactuals, Analysis, Volume 44, Issue 4, 1 October 1984, Pages 180–183, https://doi.org/10.1093/ana.
  •  61
    Naturalism, Theism, and Objects of Reason
    Philosophia Christi 15 (1): 35-45. 2013.
    It is argued that the dispute between philosophical naturalism and theism can, ultimately, only be rationally resolved in favor of theism, owing to certain internal inadequacies of philosophical naturalism that are commonly overlooked by both its friends and its foes. The criticisms of philosophical naturalism focus on certain questions concerning the ontological status of the objects of human reason and probe into the nature of human rationality and the conditions of its possibility. There is a…Read more
  •  59
    Personal Agency
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 53 211-227. 2003.
    Why does the problem of free will seem so intractable? I surmise that in large measure it does so because the free will debate, at least in its modern form, is conducted in terms of a mistaken approach to causality in general. At the heart of this approach is the assumption that all causation is fundamentally event causation. Of course, it is well-known that some philosophers of action want to invoke in addition an irreducible notion of agent causation, applicable only in the sphere of intellige…Read more
  •  58
    Is conceptualist realism a stable position? (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (2). 2005.
  •  58
    Sortal terms and natural laws
    American Philosophical Quarterly 15 (3): 253-60. 1978.
  •  58
    An analysis of intentionality
    Philosophical Quarterly 30 (October): 294-304. 1980.
  •  57
    A simplification of the logic of conditionals
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 24 (3): 357-366. 1983.