•  35
    Dissemination Corner: One True Logic
    The Reasoner 16 (1): 3-4. 2022.
    A brief article introducing *One True Logic*. The book argues that there is one correct foundational logic and that it is highly infinitary.
  •  62
    A focussed issue of The Reasoner on the topic of 'Infinitary Reasoning'. Owen Griffiths and A.C. Paseau were the guest editors.
  •  46
    Ancestral Links
    The Reasoner 16 (7): 55-56. 2022.
    This short article discusses the fact that the word ‘ancestor’ features in certain arguments that a) are apparently logically valid, b) contain infinitely many premises, and c) are such that none of their finite sub-arguments are logically valid. The article's aim is to motivate, within its brief compass, the study of infinitary logics.
  •  28
    The Euclidean Programme
    with Wesley Wrigley
    Cambridge University Press. 2024.
    The Euclidean Programme embodies a traditional sort of epistemological foundationalism, according to which knowledge – especially mathematical knowledge – is obtained by deduction from self-evident axioms or first principles. Epistemologists have examined foundationalism extensively, but neglected its historically dominant Euclidean form. By contrast, this book offers a detailed examination of Euclidean foundationalism, which, following Lakatos, the authors call the Euclidean Programme. The book…Read more
  •  132
    Lakatos and the Euclidean Programme
    with Wesley Wrigley
    In Roman Frigg, Jason Alexander, Laurenz Hudetz, Miklos Rédei, Lewis Ross & John Worrall (eds.), The Continuing Influence of Imre Lakatos's Philosophy: a Celebration of the Centenary of his Birth, Springer. forthcoming.
    Euclid’s Elements inspired a number of foundationalist accounts of mathematics, which dominated the epistemology of the discipline for many centuries in the West. Yet surprisingly little has been written by recent philosophers about this conception of mathematical knowledge. The great exception is Imre Lakatos, whose characterisation of the Euclidean Programme in the philosophy of mathematics counts as one of his central contributions. In this essay, we examine Lakatos’s account of the Euclidean…Read more
  •  142
    Non-deductive justification in mathematics
    Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. 2023.
    In mathematics, the deductive method reigns. Without proof, a claim remains unsolved, a mere conjecture, not something that can be simply assumed; when a proof is found, the problem is solved, it turns into a “result,” something that can be relied on. So mathematicians think. But is there more to mathematical justification than proof? The answer is an emphatic yes, as I explain in this article. I argue that non-deductive justification is in fact pervasive in mathematics, and that it is in good e…Read more
  •  97
    Reducing Arithmetic to Set Theory
    In Øystein Linnebo & Otavio Bueno (eds.), New Waves in Philosophy of Mathematics, Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 35-55. 2009.
    The revival of the philosophy of mathematics in the 60s following its post-1931 slump left us with two conflicting positions on arithmetic’s ontological relationship to set theory. W.V. Quine’s view, presented in 'Word and Object' (1960), was that numbers are sets. The opposing view was advanced in another milestone of twentieth-century philosophy of mathematics, Paul Benacerraf’s 'What Numbers Could Not Be' (1965): one of the things numbers could not be, it explained, was sets; the other thing …Read more
  •  91
    Letter Games: A Metamathematical Taster
    The Mathematical Gazette 100 (549): 442-449. 2016.
    The aim of this article is to give students a small sense of what metamathematics is—that is, how one might use mathematics to study mathematics itself. School or college teachers could base a classroom exercise on the letter games I shall describe and use them as a springboard for further exploration. Since I shall presuppose no knowledge of formal logic, the games are less an introduction to Gödel's theorems than an introduction to an introduction to them. Nevertheless, they show, in an access…Read more
  •  79
    Scientific Platonism
    In Mary Leng, Alexander Paseau & Michael Potter (eds.), Mathematical Knowledge, Oxford University Press. pp. 123-149. 2007.
    Does natural science give us reason to believe that mathematical statements are true? And does natural science give us reason to believe in some particular metaphysics of mathematics? These two questions should be firmly distinguished. My argument in this chapter is that a negative answer to the second question is compatible with an affirmative answer to the first. Loosely put, even if science settles the truth of mathematics, it does not settle its metaphysics.
  •  136
    Logos, Logic and Maximal Infinity
    Religious Studies 58 420-435. 2022.
  •  127
    Philosophy of Mathematics (edited book)
    Routledge. 2016.
    Mathematics is everywhere and yet its objects are nowhere. There may be five apples on the table but the number five itself is not to be found in, on, beside or anywhere near the apples. So if not in space and time, where are numbers and other mathematical objects such as perfect circles and functions? And how do we humans discover facts about them, be it Pythagoras’ Theorem or Fermat’s Last Theorem? The metaphysical question of what numbers are and the epistemological question of how we know ab…Read more
  •  27
    Indispensability
    with Alan Baker
    Cambridge University Press. 2023.
    Our best scientific theories explain a wide range of empirical phenomena, make accurate predictions, and are widely believed. Since many of these theories make ample use of mathematics, it is natural to see them as confirming its truth. Perhaps the use of mathematics in science even gives us reason to believe in the existence of abstract mathematical objects such as numbers and sets. These issues lie at the heart of the Indispensability Argument, to which this Element is devoted. The Element's f…Read more
  •  62
    One true logic: a monist manifesto
    with Owen Griffiths
    Oxford University Press. 2022.
    Logical monism is the claim that there is a single correct logic, the 'one true logic' of our title. The view has evident appeal, as it reflects assumptions made in ordinary reasoning as well as in mathematics, the sciences, and the law. In all these spheres, we tend to believe that there aredeterminate facts about the validity of arguments. Despite its evident appeal, however, logical monism must meet two challenges. The first is the challenge from logical pluralism, according to which there is…Read more
  •  58
    Deductivism in the Philosophy of Mathematics
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2023. 2023.
    Deductivism says that a mathematical sentence s should be understood as expressing the claim that s deductively follows from appropriate axioms. For instance, deductivists might construe “2+2=4” as “the sentence ‘2+2=4’ deductively follows from the axioms of arithmetic”. Deductivism promises a number of benefits. It captures the fairly common idea that mathematics is about “what can be deduced from the axioms”; it avoids an ontology of abstract mathematical objects; and it maintains that our acc…Read more
  •  24
    Compactness
    with and and Robert Leek
    Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2023.
    The Compactness Theorem The compactness theorem is a fundamental theorem for the model theory of classical propositional and first-order logic. As well as having importance in several areas of mathematics, such as algebra and combinatorics, it also helps to pinpoint the strength of these logics, which are the standard ones used in mathematics and arguably … Continue reading Compactness →
  •  46
    One Logic, Or Many?
    Philosophy Now 154 8-9. 2023.
  •  109
    Ways of Being and Logicality
    Journal of Philosophy 120 (2): 94-116. 2023.
    Ontological monists hold that there is only one way of being, while ontological pluralists hold that there are many; for example, concrete objects like tables and chairs exist in a different way from abstract objects like numbers and sets. Correspondingly, the monist will want the familiar existential quantifier as a primitive logical constant, whereas the pluralist will want distinct ones, such as for abstract and concrete existence. In this paper, we consider how the debate between the monist …Read more
  •  41
    Compactness Theorem
    with Robert Leek
    Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2022.
    The Compactness Theorem The compactness theorem is a fundamental theorem for the model theory of classical propositional and first-order logic. As well as having importance in several areas of mathematics, such as algebra and combinatorics, it also helps to pinpoint the strength of these logics, which are the standard ones used in mathematics and arguably … Continue reading Compactness Theorem →
  •  248
    Mathematical Knowledge (edited book)
    with Mary Leng and Michael D. Potter
    Oxford University Press. 2007.
    What is the nature of mathematical knowledge? Is it anything like scientific knowledge or is it sui generis? How do we acquire it? Should we believe what mathematicians themselves tell us about it? Are mathematical concepts innate or acquired? Eight new essays offer answers to these and many other questions.
  •  58
    Propositionalism
    Journal of Philosophy 118 (8): 430-449. 2021.
    Propositionalism is the claim that all logical relations can be captured by propositional logic. It is usually regarded as obviously false, because propositional logic seems too weak to capture the rich logical structure of language. I show that there is a clear sense in which propositional logic can match first-order logic, by producing formalizations that are valid iff their first-order counterparts are, and also respect grammatical form as the propositionalist construes it. I explain the real…Read more
  •  45
    Is English consequence compact?
    Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 10 (3): 188-198. 2021.
    Thought: A Journal of Philosophy, Volume 10, Issue 3, Page 188-198, September 2021.
  •  32
    Arithmetic, enumerative induction and size bias
    Synthese 199 (3-4): 9161-9184. 2021.
    Number theory abounds with conjectures asserting that every natural number has some arithmetic property. An example is Goldbach’s Conjecture, which states that every even number greater than 2 is the sum of two primes. Enumerative inductive evidence for such conjectures usually consists of small cases. In the absence of supporting reasons, mathematicians mistrust such evidence for arithmetical generalisations, more so than most other forms of non-deductive evidence. Some philosophers have also e…Read more
  •  86
    Non-metric Propositional Similarity
    Erkenntnis 87 (5): 2307-2328. 2022.
    The idea that sentences can be closer or further apart in meaning is highly intuitive. Not only that, it is also a pillar of logic, semantic theory and the philosophy of science, and follows from other commitments about similarity. The present paper proposes a novel way of comparing the ‘distance’ between two pairs of propositions. We define ‘\ is closer in meaning to \ than \ is to \’ and thereby give a precise account of comparative propositional similarity facts. Notably, our definition esche…Read more
  •  77
    Justin Clarke-Doane* Morality and Mathematics
    with Michael Bevan
    Philosophia Mathematica 28 (3): 442-446. 2020.
    _Justin Clarke-Doane* * Morality and Mathematics. _ Oxford University Press, 2020. Pp. xx + 208. ISBN: 978-0-19-882366-7 ; 978-0-19-2556806.† †
  •  95
    A measure of inferential-role preservation
    Synthese 196 (7): 2621-2642. 2019.
    The point of formalisation is to model various aspects of natural language. Perhaps the main use to which formalisation is put is to model and explain inferential relations between different sentences. Judged solely by this objective, a formalisation is successful in modelling the inferential network of natural language sentences to the extent that it mirrors this network. There is surprisingly little literature on the criteria of good formalisation, and even less on the question of what it is f…Read more
  •  74
    Capturing Consequence
    Review of Symbolic Logic 12 (2): 271-295. 2019.
    First-order formalisations are often preferred to propositional ones because they are thought to underwrite the validity of more arguments. We compare and contrast the ability of some well-known logics—these two in particular—to formally capture valid and invalid arguments. We show that there is a precise and important sense in which first-order logic does not improve on propositional logic in this respect. We also prove some generalisations and related results of philosophical interest. The re…Read more
  •  47