•  64
    Logic and Philosophy: a modern introduction
    Wadsworth, Cengage Learning. 2013.
    As the title suggests, this is a book devoted not merely to logic; students will also examine the philosophical debates that led to the development of the field.
  •  51
  •  42
    Introduction to Logic (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 1 (2): 194-200. 1975.
  •  42
    Reasoning (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 2 (3-4): 328-335. 1977.
  •  40
    Descartes’s Secular Semantics
    with David Hausman
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (1). 1992.
    … if we bear well in mind the scope of our senses and what it is exactly that reaches our faculty of thinking by way of them, we must admit that in no case are the ideas of things presented to us by the senses just as we form them in our thinking. So much so that there is nothing in our ideas which is not innate to the mind or the faculty of thinking, with the sole exception of those circumstances which relate to experience, such as the fact that we judge that this or that idea which we now have…Read more
  •  39
    Descartes' Dualism (review)
    with David B. Hausman
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 36 (2): 318-320. 1998.
    318 JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY 36:2 APRIL 1998 stress should not be placed on Spinoza's excommunication . One among many who held radical views and during a period of unrest brought on by an influx of emigration, Spinoza was dealt the same punishment as those who failed to pay their communal dues. The apt conclusion drawn is that from the perspective of the commu- nity, this excommunication was of no great significance. Such history corrects earlier interpretations and helps readers to…Read more
  •  36
    When Keats identified truth and beauty, he surely intended mere extensionality. I myself have never had much trouble with either half of the equivalence. Others have considerable difficulty. A case in point is the Watson-Allaire-Cummins interpretation of Berkeley's idealism, which I shall refer to henceforth as the inherence account. That account is put forward to answer an extremely perplexing question in the history of philosophy: Why did Berkeley embrace idealism, i.e., why did he hold that e…Read more
  •  35
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:IT AIN'T NECESSITY, SO... (With Apologies to George Gershwin) I shall argue in this paper that what Hume calls the idea of necessary connection is mislabelled, and that what he ought to call the idea of necessary connection is not so labelled. My argument is not that there are, on Hume's view, real necessary connections between causes and their effects but rather that there is an idea of genuine necessary connection — what I call log…Read more
  •  33
    Is everything a class?
    with Tom Foster
    Philosophical Studies 32 (4). 1977.
  •  30
    7. Berkeley and the Argument from Perceptual Variation
    with David Hausman
    In David B. Hausman & Alan Hausman (eds.), Descartes’s Legacy: Minds and Meaning in Early Modern Philosophy, University of Toronto Press. pp. 99-111. 1997.
  •  25
    A New Approach to Berkeley's Ideal Reality
    with David Hausman
    In Robert G. Muehlmann (ed.), Berkeley's Metaphysics: Structural, Interpretive, and Critical Essays, The Pennsylvania State University Press. pp. 65-78. 1995.
  •  20
    IV. Strawson on the traditional logic
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 12 (1-4): 254-259. 1969.
    In his Introduction to Logical Theory, Strawson argues that Aristotelian logic can be given a successful interpretation into ordinary English, but not into the symbolism of Principia Mathematica, on the grounds that Aristotelian logic and ordinary English share something absent in PM, namely, the doctrine of presupposition. It is argued that Strawson is mistaken. PM does justice to the logical rules of Aristotelian logic and also has a fully articulated doctrine of presupposition
  •  20
    Berkeley's Semantic Dilemma: Beyond the Inherence Model
    with David Hausman
    History of Philosophy Quarterly 13 (2). 1996.
  •  19
    Some Counsel on Humean Relations
    Hume Studies 1 (2): 48-65. 1975.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:48 SOME CQUHSEL ON HUMEAN RELATIONS In a paper published eight years ago I tried to bring out a neglected feature of Hume's theory of relations, namely the difference between philosophical and natural re1 2. lations. Now Ijnlay, without referring to my work, has expanded some of its themes in an extremely interesting and, I think, important way. At least he has made me rethink the whole distinction between philosophical and natural r…Read more
  •  18
    Cartwright, classes, and criterial difference
    with Tom Foster
    Noûs 12 (3): 329-336. 1978.
  •  18
    Frontmatter
    with David Hausman
    In David B. Hausman & Alan Hausman (eds.), Descartes’s Legacy: Minds and Meaning in Early Modern Philosophy, University of Toronto Press. 1997.
  •  18
    Identifying identity
    with James S. Kelly
    Erkenntnis 25 (3). 1986.
    Nelson Goodman argues against those who, like Carnap, claim extensional identity is the criterion for correct constructional definition. Goodman argues that internal logical difficulties sink such a criterion, thus he proposes his own criterion of extensional isomorphism. We argue that Goodman's criterion itself falls prey to his own arguments or else extensional identity is not shown faulty
  •  16
    The Breakdown of Cartesian Metaphysics
    Noûs 27 (2): 272-275. 1993.
  •  15
    Carnap and Goodman: Two Formalists
    with Fred Wilson
    Philosophy of Science 36 (3): 327-330. 1969.
  •  14
    5. A New Approach to Berkeley's Ideal Reality
    with David Hausman
    In David B. Hausman & Alan Hausman (eds.), Descartes’s Legacy: Minds and Meaning in Early Modern Philosophy, University of Toronto Press. pp. 65-78. 1997.
  •  13
    Howard Kahane, 1928-2001
    with Charles Landesman and Roger Seamon
    Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 75 (5). 2002.
  •  13
    Descartes’s Legacy: Minds and Meaning in Early Modern Philosophy
    with David B. Hausman
    University of Toronto Press. 1997.
    The Hausmans wed an intentional theory of ideas with a modern information theoretic approach in a critical tour of some of the most important issues in the philosophy of mind and some of the most outstanding figures in early modern philosophy.
  •  12
    6. Hume's Use of Illicit Substances
    with David Hausman
    In David B. Hausman & Alan Hausman (eds.), Descartes’s Legacy: Minds and Meaning in Early Modern Philosophy, University of Toronto Press. pp. 79-98. 1997.
  •  11
    Contents
    with David Hausman
    In David B. Hausman & Alan Hausman (eds.), Descartes’s Legacy: Minds and Meaning in Early Modern Philosophy, University of Toronto Press. 1997.
  •  10
    Subject Index
    with David Hausman
    In David B. Hausman & Alan Hausman (eds.), Descartes’s Legacy: Minds and Meaning in Early Modern Philosophy, University of Toronto Press. pp. 145-148. 1997.
  •  9
    2. Descartes's Semantic Intentions
    with David Hausman
    In David B. Hausman & Alan Hausman (eds.), Descartes’s Legacy: Minds and Meaning in Early Modern Philosophy, University of Toronto Press. pp. 13-28. 1997.
  •  8
    Acknowledgments
    with David Hausman
    In David B. Hausman & Alan Hausman (eds.), Descartes’s Legacy: Minds and Meaning in Early Modern Philosophy, University of Toronto Press. 1997.
  •  8
    Notes
    with David Hausman
    In David B. Hausman & Alan Hausman (eds.), Descartes’s Legacy: Minds and Meaning in Early Modern Philosophy, University of Toronto Press. pp. 117-138. 1997.