•  534
    “The Scalar Approach to Utilitarianism”
    In Henry West (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Mill's Utilitarianism, Wiley-blackwell. pp. 217--32. 2008.
    This chapter contains section titled: Introduction The Demandingness Objection Scalar Utilitarianism Wrongness as Blameworthiness Rightness and Goodness as Guides to Action.
  •  449
  •  305
    One of the currently popular dogmata of anti-consequentialism is that consequentialism doesn't respect, recognize, or in some important way account for what is referred to as the The charge is often made, but rarely explained in any detail, much less argued for. In this paper I explain what I take to be the most plausible interpretation of the separateness of persons charge. I argue that the charge itself can be deconstructed into at least two further objections to consequentialist theories. The…Read more
  •  268
    Frances Kamm's aptly titled Intricate Ethics is a tour de force of what Peter Unger calls the ‘preservationist’ approach to ethical theory. Here is some of what she says about her methodology: Consider as many case-based judgments of yours as prove necessary. Do not ignore some case-based judgments, assuming they are errors, just because they conflict with simple or intuitively plausible principles that account for some subset of your case-based judgments. Work on the assumption that a different…Read more
  •  233
    Killing and letting die (edited book)
    with Bonnie Steinbock
    Fordham University Press. 1994.
    This collection contains twenty-one thought-provoking essays on the controversies surrounding the moral and legal distinctions between euthanasia and "letting die." Since public awareness of this issue has increased this second edition includes nine entirely new essays which bring the treatment of the subject up-to-date. The urgency of this issue can be gauged in recent developments such as the legalization of physician-assisted suicide in the Netherlands, "how-to" manuals topping the bestseller…Read more
  •  217
    The Impotence of the Causal Impotence Objection
    Southwest Philosophy Review 36 (1): 161-168. 2020.
    Many significant harms, such as the mass suffering of animals on factory farms, can only be prevented, or at least lessened, by the collective action of thousands, or in some cases millions, of individual agents. In the face of this, it can seem as if individuals are powerless to make a difference, and thus that they lack reasons, at least from the consequentialist perspective, to refrain from eating meat. This has become known as the “causal impotence” problem. The standard response is to appea…Read more
  •  217
    Suppose that a very large number of people, say one billion, will suffer a moderately severe headache for the next twenty-four hours. For these billion people, the next twenty-four hours will be fairly unpleasant, though by no means unbearable. However, there will be no side-effects from these headaches; no drop in productivity in the work-place, no lapses in concentration leading to accidents, no unkind words spoken to loved ones that will later fester. Nonetheless, it is clearly desirable that…Read more
  •  213
    In these comments on Fred Feldman's Pleasure and the Good Life, I first challenge the dichotomy between sensory and attitudinal hedonisms as perhaps presenting a false dilemma. I suggest that there may be a form of hedonism that employs the concept of a that is not purely sensory. Next, I raise some problems for several of the versions of hedonism explored in the book
  •  198
    Torturing Puppies and Eating Meat
    Southwest Philosophy Review 20 (1): 117-123. 2004.
  •  171
    Good and bad actions
    Philosophical Review 106 (1): 1-34. 1997.
    It is usually assumed to be possible, and sometimes even desirable, for consequentialists to make judgments about both the rightness and the goodness of actions. Whether a particular action is right or wrong is one question addressed by a consequentialist theory such as utilitarianism. Whether the action is good or bad, and how good or bad it is, are two others. I will argue in this paper that consequentialism cannot provide a satisfactory account of the goodness of actions, on the most natural …Read more
  •  161
    Causal Impotence and Eating Meat
    Southwest Philosophy Review 24 (2): 5-10. 2008.
  •  158
    Intransitivity and the person-affecting principle
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (3): 769-776. 1999.
    Philosophy journals and conferences have recently seen several attempts to argue that 'all-things-considered better than' does not obey strict transitivity. This paper focuses on Larry Temkin's argument in "Intransitivity and the Mere Addition Paradox." Although his argument is not aimed just at utilitarians or even consequentialists in general, it is of prticular significance to consequentialists. If 'all-things-considered better than' does not obey transitivity, there may be choice situations …Read more
  •  126
    Contractualism and Aggregation
    Social Theory and Practice 28 (2): 303-314. 2002.
  •  116
    Harming In Context
    Philosophical Studies 123 (1-2): 149-173. 2005.
  •  113
    Consequentialism and commitment
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 78 (4). 1997.
    It is sometimes claimed that a consequentialist theory such as utilitarianism has problems accommodating the importance of personal commitments to other people. However, by emphasizing the distinction between criteria of rightness and decision procedures, a consequentialist can allow for non-consequentialist decision procedures, such as acting directly on the promptings of natural affection. Furthermore, such non-consequentialist motivational structures can co-exist happily with a commitment to …Read more
  •  110
    If consequentialism is understood as claiming, at least, that the moral character of an action depends only on the consequences of the action, it might be thought that the difficulty of knowing what all the consequences of any action will be poses a problem for consequentialism. J. J. C. Smart writes that in most cases..
  •  103
    Contextualism for consequentialists
    Acta Analytica 20 (2): 80-90. 2005.
    If, as I have argued elsewhere, consequentialism is not fundamentally concerned with such staples of moral theory as rightness, duty, obligation, moral requirements, goodness (as applied to actions), and harm, what, if anything, does it have to say about such notions? While such notions have no part to play at the deepest level of the theory, they may nonetheless be of practical significance. By way of explanation I provide a linguistic contextualist account of these notions. A contextualist app…Read more
  •  91
    A Consequentialist Case for Rejecting the Right
    Journal of Philosophical Research 18 109-125. 1993.
    Satisficing and maximizing versions of consequentialism have both assumed that rightness is an alI-or-nothing property. We argue thal this is inimical to the spirit of consequentialism, and that, from the point of view of the consequentialist, actions should be evaluated purely in terms that admit of degree. We first consider the suggestion that rightness and wrongness are a matter of degree. If so, this raises the question of whether the claim that something is wrong says any more than that it …Read more
  •  87
  •  85
    Reasons without demands: Rethinking rightness
    In James Lawrence Dreier (ed.), Contemporary Debates in Moral Theory, Blackwell. pp. 38--54. 2006.
  •  79
    Beastly Violence, or How Kant Screws Everything up Yet Again
    Southwest Philosophy Review 27 (2): 63-66. 2011.
  •  70
    Animal experimentation
    In Bonnie Steinbock (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Bioethics, Oxford University Press. 2007.
    This article takes the central issue concerning the ethics of animal experimentation to be the moral status of animals. Since most animal experimentation involves treating experimental subjects in ways that would clearly not be morally acceptable if the subjects were human, and since no animal experimentation involves the informed consent of the experimental subject, any attempt to justify such experimentation must include a defense of the claim that the moral status of animals differs significa…Read more
  •  67
    Moral Intuitions and fMRI Research
    Southwest Philosophy Review 25 (2): 19-23. 2009.
  •  60
    Trading Lives for Convenience
    Southwest Philosophy Review 13 (1): 29-37. 1997.
  •  60