•  36
    In defense of pure reason
    Philosophical Review 109 (1): 103-107. 2000.
    This book is an important contribution to the contemporary epistemological literature. It is the only available book-length treatment of epistemological issues associated with the a priori. Moreover, it provides the most comprehensive articulation and defense of traditional rationalism. The book is tightly organized, crisply argued, and sets the standard against which competing accounts must be measured.
  • Modality and a priori knowledge
    In Otávio Bueno & Scott A. Shalkowski (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Modality, Routledge. 2018.
  •  38
    Is Knowledge of Essence the Basis of Modal Knowledge?
    Res Philosophica 97 (4): 593-609. 2020.
    E. J. Lowe offers an account of modal knowledge that involves two primary theses. First, the basis of modal knowledge is essential knowledge, and the source of essential knowledge is grasp of essence. Second, all empirical knowledge ultimately depends on some modal knowledge. This article assesses Lowe’s account and defends four conclusions. First, there is a tension in Lowe’s account of grasp of essence; it wavers between an undemanding version, which holds that grasp of essence requires no mor…Read more
  •  46
    Modal Empiricism: What is the Problem
    Oxford Studies in Epistemology 6. 2019.
    Kant contends that necessity is a criterion of the a priori—that is, that all knowledge of necessary propositions is a priori. This contention, together with two others that Kant took to be evident—we know some mathematical propositions and such propositions are necessary—leads directly to the conclusion that some knowledge is a priori. Although many contemporary philosophers endorse Kant’s criterion, supporting arguments are hard to come by. Gordon Barnes provides one of the few examples. My pu…Read more
  •  400
    Essence and Explanation
    Metaphysics 2 (1): 88-96. 2020.
    In Necessary Beings, Bob Hale addresses two questions: What is the source of necessity? What is the source of our knowledge of it? He offers novel responses to them in terms of the metaphysical notion of nature or, more familiarly, essence. In this paper, I address Hale’s response to the first question. My assessment is negative. I argue that his essentialist explanation of the source of necessity suffers from three significant shortcomings. First, Hale’s leading example of an essentialist expla…Read more
  •  368
    Christopher Hill contends that the metaphysical modalities can be reductively explained in terms of the subjunctive conditional and that this reductive explanation yields two tests for determining the metaphysical modality of a proposition. He goes on to argue that his reductive account of the metaphysical modalities in conjunction with his account of modal knowledge underwrites the further conclusion that conceivability does not provide a reliable test for metaphysical possibility. I argue (1) …Read more
  •  15
    Essays on a Priori Knowledge and Justification (edited book)
    Oup Usa. 2014.
    The past twenty-five years have seen a major renewal of interest in the topic of a priori knowledge. In the sixteen essays collected here, which span this entire period, philosopher Albert Casullo documents the complex set of issues motivating the renewed interest, identifies the central epistemological questions, and provides the leading ideas of a unified response to them.
  •  1
  •  3
    Conceivability and possibility
    Ratio (Misc.) 17 (1): 118-121. 1975.
    The purpose of this article is to defend Hume's claim that whatever is conceivable is possible from a criticism by William Kneale. Kneale argues that although a mathematician can conceive of the falsehood of the Goldbach conjecture, he does not conclude that it is not necessarily true. The author suggests that by taking into account Hume's distinction between intuitive and demonstrative knowledge, a revised version of his claim can be offered which is not open to Kneale's criticism.
  •  112
    Revisability, reliabilism, and a priori knowledge
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 49 (2): 187-213. 1988.
  •  253
    A selective annotated bibliography of recent literature on a priori knowledge.
  •  801
    The distinction between a priori knowledge and a posteriori knowledge has come under attack in the recent literature by Philip Kitcher, John Hawthorne, C. S. Jenkins, and Timothy Williamson. Evaluating the attacks requires answering two questions. First, have they hit their target? Second, are they compelling? My goal is to argue that the attacks fail because they miss their target. Since the attacks are directed at a particular concept or distinction, they must accurately locate the target conc…Read more
  •  18
    Kripke on the "a priori" and the necessary
    Analysis 37 (4): 152. 1977.
  •  92
    Grounding Concepts, by C. S. Jenkins.: Book Reviews (review)
    Mind 119 (475): 805-810. 2010.
    (No abstract is available for this citation)
  •  247
    What is entitlement?
    Acta Analytica 22 (4). 2007.
    In his seminal paper, Content Preservation, Tyler Burge defends an original account of testimonial knowledge. The originality of the account is due, in part, to the fact that it is cast within a novel epistemic framework. The central feature of that framework is the introduction of the concept of entitlement, which is alleged to be a distinctive type of positive epistemic support or warrant. Entitlement and justification, according to Burge, are sub-species of warrant. Justification is the inter…Read more
  •  88
    Defeasible a priori justification: A reply to Thurow
    Philosophical Quarterly 58 (231). 2008.
    Joshua Thurow offers a defence of the claim that if a belief is defeasible by non-experiential evidence then it is defeasible by experiential evidence. He responds to an objection which I make against this claim, and offers two arguments in support of his own position. I show that Thurow's response misconstrues my objection, and that his supporting arguments fall short of their goal.
  •  102
    The a Priori in Philosophy (edited book)
    with Albert Casullo and Joshua C. Thurow
    Oxford University Press UK. 2013.
    For much of the past two millennia philosophers have embraced a priori knowledge and have thought that the a priori plays an important role in philosophy itself. Philosophers from Plato to Descartes, Kant to Kripke, all endorse the a priori and engage in a priori reasoning in their philosophical discussions. Recent work in epistemology and experimental philosophy, however, has raised questions about both the existence of a priori knowledge and the centrality of the a priori for philosophy. This …Read more
  •  294
    Knowledge, A Priori
    In D. M. Borchert (ed.), Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd ed, . pp. 79-86. 2006.
  •  141
    Reid and Mill on Hume's Maxim of Conceivability
    Analysis 39 (4): 212--219. 1979.
    Hume's maxim consists of two principles which are logically independent of each other: (1) whatever is conceivable is possible; and (2) whatever is inconceivable is impossible. Thomas Reid offered several arguments against the former principle, while John Stuart mill argued against the latter. The primary concern of this paper is to examine whether Reid and mill were successful in calling Hume's maxim into question.
  •  192
    Analyzing a priori knowledge
    Philosophical Studies 142 (1). 2009.
    There are four approaches to analyzing the concept of a priori knowledge. The primary target of the reductive approach is the concept of a priori justification. The primary target of the nonreductive approach is the concept of a priori knowledge. There are two approaches to analyzing each primary target. A theory-neutral approach provides an analysis that does not presuppose any general theory of knowledge or justification. A theory-laden approach provides an analysis that does presuppose some g…Read more
  •  32
    On "A Definition of A Priori Knowledge"
    Journal of Critical Analysis 7 (2): 43-46. 1978.
  •  248
    Knowledge and modality
    Synthese 172 (3). 2010.
    Kripke claims that there are necessary a posteriori truths and contingent a priori truths. These claims challenge the traditional Kantian view that (K)  All knowledge of necessary truths is a priori and all a priori knowledge is of necessary truths. Kripke’s claims continue to be resisted, which indicates that the Kantian view remains attractive. My goal is to identify the most plausible principles linking the epistemic and the modal. My strategy for identifying the principles is to investigate …Read more
  •  106
    Epistemic Overdetermination and A Priori Justification
    Philosophical Perspectives 19 (1): 41-58. 2005.
    Radical empiricism is the view that experience is the only source of knowledge. Hence, radical empiricism denies the existence of a priori knowledge. Its most famous proponents are John Stuart Mill and W. V. Quine. Although both reject a priori knowledge, they offer different empiricist accounts of the knowledge alleged by their opponents to be a priori. My primary concern in this paper is not with the cogency of their positive accounts. My focus is their arguments against a priori knowledge. My…Read more
  •  150
    The spatial structure of perceptual space
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 46 (4): 665-671. 1986.
  •  59
    Conjunctive properties revisited
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62 (3). 1984.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  127
    A defense of sense-data
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48 (September): 45-61. 1987.
  •  64
    Phenomenal properties
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 60 (2): 165-169. 1982.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  135
    Modal Epistemology: Fortune or Virtue?
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 38 (S1): 17-25. 2000.