•  3688
    Human beings among the beasts
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 102 (3): 455-467. 2021.
    In this article, we develop and defend a new argument for animalism -- the thesis that we human persons are human animals. The argument takes this rough form: since our pets are animals, we are too. We’ll begin with remarks on animalism and its rivals, develop our main argument, and then defend it against a few replies.
  •  611
    The Hume-Edwards principle and the cosmological argument
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 43 (3): 149-165. 1998.
  •  572
    Nestes Modes, ’Qua’ and the Incarnation
    European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 6 (2): 65--80. 2014.
    A nested mode ontology allows one to make sense of apparently contradictory Christological claims such as that Christ knows everything and there are some things Christ does not know.
  •  537
    Evil and the problem of anomaly
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion 5 49-87. 2014.
  •  536
    On Two Problems of Divine Simplicity
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion 1 150-167. 2008.
  •  525
    Being Sure and Being Confident That You Won’t Lose Confidence
    Logos and Episteme 7 (1): 45-54. 2016.
    There is an important sense in which one can be sure without being certain, i.e., without assigning unit probability. I will offer an explication of this sense of sureness, connecting it with the level of credence that a rational agent would need to have to be confident that she won’t ever lose her confidence. A simple formal result then gives us an explicit formula connecting the threshold α for credence needed for confidence with the threshold needed for being sure: one needs 1−(1−α) to be sur…Read more
  •  498
  •  497
    A new cosmological argument
    with Richard M. Gale
    Religious Studies 35 (4): 461-476. 1999.
    We will give a new cosmological argument for the existence of a being who, although not proved to be the absolutely perfect God of the great Medieval theists, also is capable of playing the role in the lives of working theists of a being that is a suitable object of worship, adoration, love, respect, and obedience. Unlike the absolutely perfect God, the God whose necessary existence is established by our argument will not be shown to essentially have the divine perfections of omnipotence, omnisc…Read more
  •  483
    Understanding Omnipotence
    Religious Studies 48 (3): 403-414. 2012.
    An omnipotent being would be a being whose power was unlimited. The power of human beings is limited in two distinct ways: we are limited with respect to our freedom of will, and we are limited in our ability to execute what we have willed. These two distinct sources of limitation suggest a simple definition of omnipotence: an omnipotent being is one that has both perfect freedom of will and perfect efficacy of will. In this paper we further explicate this definition and show that it escapes the…Read more
  •  410
    Skepticism and the principle of sufficient reason
    Philosophical Studies 178 (4): 1079-1099. 2020.
    The Principle of Sufficient Reason must be justified dialectically: by showing the disastrous consequences of denying it. We formulate a version of the Principle that is restricted to basic natural facts, which entails the obtaining of at least one supernatural fact. Denying this principle results in extreme empirical skepticism. We consider six current theories of empirical knowledge, showing that on each account we cannot know that we have empirical knowledge unless we all have a priori knowle…Read more
  •  385
    Probability, Regularity, and Cardinality
    Philosophy of Science 80 (2): 231-240. 2013.
    Regularity is the thesis that all contingent propositions should be assigned probabilities strictly between zero and one. I will prove on cardinality grounds that if the domain is large enough, a regular probability assignment is impossible, even if we expand the range of values that probabilities can take, including, for instance, hyperreal values, and significantly weaken the axioms of probability.
  •  329
    The Principle of Sufficient Reason: A Reassessment
    Cambridge University Press. 2006.
    The Principle of Sufficient Reason says that all contingent facts must have explanation. In this 2006 volume, which was the first on the topic in the English language in nearly half a century, Alexander Pruss examines the substantive philosophical issues raised by the Principle Reason. Discussing various forms of the PSR and selected historical episodes, from Parmenides, Leibnez, and Hume, Pruss defends the claim that every true contingent proposition must have an explanation against major objec…Read more
  •  294
    The Leibnizian Cosmological Argument
    In William Lane Craig & J. P. Moreland (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology, Wiley‐blackwell. 2009.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Introduction The PSR Nonlocal CPs Toward a First Cause The Gap Problem Conclusions and Further Research References.
  •  291
    A response to Oppy, and to Davey and Clifton
    with Richard M. Gale
    Religious Studies 38 (1): 89-99. 2002.
    Our paper ‘A new cosmological argument’ gave an argument for the existence of God making use of the weak Principle of Sufficient Reason (W-PSR) which states that for every proposition p, if p is true, then it is possible that there is an explanation for p. Recently, Graham Oppy, as well as Kevin Davey and Rob Clifton, have criticized the argument. We reply to these criticisms. The most interesting kind of criticism in both papers alleges that the W-PSR can be justifiably denied by the atheist, a…Read more
  •  284
    Might All Infinities Be the Same Size?
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 98 (3): 604-617. 2020.
    Cantor proved that no set has a bijection between itself and its power set. This is widely taken to have shown that there infinitely many sizes of infinite sets. The argument depends on the princip...
  •  275
    Incompatibilism proved
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 43 (4): 430-437. 2013.
    (2013). Incompatibilism proved. Canadian Journal of Philosophy. ???aop.label???
  •  238
    A gödelian ontological argument improved
    Religious Studies 45 (3): 347-353. 2009.
    Gödel's ontological argument is a formal argument for a being defined in terms of the concept of a positive property. I shall defend several versions of Gödel's argument, using weaker premises than Anderson's (1990) version, and avoiding Oppy's (1996 and 2000) parody refutations
  •  206
    A Counterexample to Plantinga’s Free Will Defense
    Faith and Philosophy 29 (4): 400-415. 2012.
    Plantinga’s Free Will Defense is an argument that, possibly, God cannot actualize a world containing significant creaturely free will and no wrongdoings. I will argue that if standard Molinism is true, there is a pair of worlds w1 and w2 each of which contains a significantly free creature who never chooses wrongly, and that are such that, necessarily, at least one of these worlds is a world that God can actualize.
  •  190
    David Lewis (1979) has argued that according to his possible worlds analysis of counterfactuals, “backtracking” counterfactuals of the form “If event A were to happen at tA, then event B would happen at tB” where tB precedes tA, are usually false if B does not actually happen at tB. On the other..
  •  188
    The cardinality objection to David Lewis's modal realism
    Philosophical Studies 104 (2): 169-178. 2001.
    According to David Lewis's extreme modal realism, every waythat a world could be is a way that some concretely existingphysical world really is. But if the worlds are physicalentities, then there should be a set of all worlds, whereasI show that in fact the collection of all possible worlds is nota set. The latter conclusion remains true even outside of theLewisian framework.
  •  184
    We show that infinitesimal probabilities are much too small for modeling the individual outcome of a countably infinite fair lottery
  •  179
    Omnirationality
    Res Philosophica 90 (1): 1-21. 2013.
    God is omnirational: whenever he does anything, he does it for all and only the unexcluded reasons that favor the action, and he always acts for reasons. Thisdoctrine has two unexpected consequences: it gives an account of why it is that unification is a genuine form of scientific explanation, and it answers the question of when the occurrence of E after a petitionary prayer for E is an answer to the prayer
  •  177
    Possibility is not consistency
    Philosophical Studies 172 (9): 2341-2348. 2015.
    We shall use Gödel’s Second Incompleteness Theorem to show that consistency is not possibility, and then argue that the argument does serious damage to some theories of modality where consistency plays a major but not exclusive role
  •  169
    Another Step in Divine Command Dialectics
    Faith and Philosophy 26 (4): 432-439. 2009.
    Consider the following three-step dialectics. (1) Even if God (consistently) commanded torture of the innocent, it would still be wrong. Therefore Divine Command Metaethics (DCM) is false. (2) No: for it is impossible for God to command torture of the innocent. (3) Even if it is impossible, there is a non-trivially true per impossibile counterfactual that even if God (consistently) com­manded torture of the innocent, it would still be wrong, and this counterfac­tual is incompatible with DCM. I s…Read more
  •  168
    The Eucharist : real presence and real absence
    In Thomas P. Flint & Michael Rea (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Theology, Oxford University Press. 2008.
    This article focuses on the question of whether the doctrine of the real presence of Christ's body and blood, and likewise the doctrine of the real absence of bread and wine, can be defended philosophically. It argues for an affirmative answer, and does so by considering a variety of metaphysical models, including that of Aquinas. It will appear, thus, that transubstantiation is a philosophical possibility. If it is possible for two substances to be in the same place at the same time, consubstan…Read more
  •  163
    Review of Graham Oppy, Arguing About Gods (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2007 (5). 2007.
  •  159
    The classical principle of double effect offers permissibility conditions for actions foreseen to lead to evil outcomes. I shall argue that certain kinds of closeness cases, as well as general heuristic considerations about the order of explanation, lead us to replace the intensional concept of intention with the extensional concept of accomplishment in double effect
  •  157
    Conditional probabilities
    Analysis 72 (3): 488-491. 2012.
    A simple argument is given that shows that conditional probabilities do not supervene on unconditional probabilities. In particular, one cannot in general define conditional probabilities using the ratio formula P ( U | V ) = P ( U & V )/ P ( U ), or using any more sophisticated method based on unconditional probabilities
  •  152
    Prophecy without middle knowledge
    Faith and Philosophy 24 (4): 433-457. 2007.
    While it might seem prima facie plausible that divine foreknowledge is all that is needed for prophecy, this seems incorrect. To issue a prophecy, God hasto know not just how someone will act, but how someone would act were the prophecy issued. This makes some think that Middle Knowledge is required.I argue that Thomas Flint’s two Middle Knowledge based accounts of prophecy are unsatisfactory, but one of them can be repaired. However the resources needed for repair also yield a sketch of a forek…Read more