•  149
    David Pérez Chico & Luisa Paz Rodríguez Suárez, eds. 2011. Explicar y Comprender (A. Velasco Gómez) (review)
    Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 28 (1): 167-169. 2013.
  •  60
    Aristotle’s Hypotheses and the Euclidean Postulates
    Review of Metaphysics 30 (3). 1977.
    I would like to challenge this view on various grounds, but before I do so, I wish to provide a broader setting for the problems discussed in this paper.
  •  54
    IN THE first chapter of the second book of the Analytica Posteriora Aristotle offers a fourfold classification of objects of inquiry He refers to each of them by means of a shorthand expression
  •  19
    Ethics with Aristotle (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (3): 728-731. 1995.
    The author’s declared goal in this book is to convey “what has registered with [her] as crucial for the understanding of Aristotle’s ethics”. There is no lack of direct philosophical argumentation in this valuable work, but if we had to classify it by its contents, we would be well advised to place it on our shelves among the commentaries on the Nicomachean Ethics.
  •  56
    On the Ethical Evaluation of Stem Cell Research: Remarks on a Paper by N. Knoepffler
    Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 14 (1): 75-80. 2004.
    : This response to Nikolaus Knoepffler's paper in the same issue of the Journal agrees that if the arguments supporting the first two of the eight human embryonic stem cell research policy options discussed are unsound, as Knoepffler argues, then it seems natural to move to the increasingly permissive options. If the arguments are sound, however, then the more permissive options should be rejected. It is argued that three of the rejected arguments, taken together, constitute very good reasons to…Read more
  •  25
    The Foundations of Socratic Ethics
    Philosophical Review 105 (2): 233. 1996.
    Self-interest theories hold that rationality requires one always to choose what is best for oneself. Where these theories differ is in their accounts of what is best for one. Hedonism is a typical self-interest theory, distinguished from other versions by the claim that what is best for one is what gives one the greatest net balance of pleasure over pain. Gómez-Lobo thinks that Socrates is a self-interest theorist: Socrates believes that “a choice is rational if and only if it is a choice of wha…Read more
  •  81
    Does respect for embryos entail respect for gametes?
    Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 25 (3): 199-208. 2004.
    Respect for human embryos is often defended on the basis of the potentiality argument: embryos deserve respect because they already possess potentially the features that in adults are fully actualized. Opponents of this argument challenge it by claiming that if embryos should be respected because they are potentially adults, then gametes should be respected because they are potentially embryos. This article rejects this reductio ad absurdum argument by showing that there are two different types …Read more
  •  6
    Colloquium 6
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 5 (1): 181-203. 1989.
  •  165
    A note on metaphysics and embryology
    Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 28 (4): 331-335. 2007.
  •  100
    The Ergon Inference
    Phronesis 34 (1): 170-184. 1989.
  •  39
    Natural Law and Naturalism
    Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 59 (n/a): 232. 1985.
  •  7
    On the mobility of dislocations in germanium and silicon
    with P. B. Hirsch
    Philosophical Magazine 36 (1): 169-179. 1977.
  •  174
    On potentiality and respect for embryos: A reply to Mary Mahowald
    Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 26 (2): 105-110. 2005.
    In order to understand the nature of human embryos I first distinguish between active and passive potentiality, and then argue that the former is found in human gametes and embryos (even in embryos in vitro that may fail to be implanted) because they all have an indwelling power or capacity to initiate certain changes. Implantation provides necessary conditions for the actualization of that prior, active potentiality. This does not imply that embryos are potential persons that do not deserve the…Read more
  •  13
    Las Teorías del Sueño en La Filosofia Antigua (review)
    Ancient Philosophy 11 (2): 445-447. 1991.
  •  10
    Individuality and Human Beginnings: A Reply to David DeGrazia
    Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 35 (3): 457-462. 2007.
    In a recent article published in the Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, David DeGrazia criticized the two pivotal assumptions that underlie President Bush’s policy on funding stem cell research. Those assumptions are that we originate as single-cell zygotes at the time of conception and that we have full moral status as soon as we originate.In this paper, I would like to concentrate on the first of those assumptions and show in light of recent findings in embryological development that DeGrazia’…Read more
  •  27
    Individuality and Human Beginnings: A Reply to David DeGrazia
    Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 35 (3): 457-462. 2007.
    The author argues that individuality does not require indivisibility and that twinning can be explained as the reprogramming of blastomeres that already have begun to differentiate in accordance with the needs of the unified organism that originates at conception
  •  86
    Inviolability at any age
    Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 17 (4): 311-320. 2007.
    : This paper starts from three assumptions: that we are essentially human organisms, that we start to exist at conception, and that we retain our identity throughout our lives. The identity claim provides the background to argue that it is irrational for a person to claim that it would be impermissible to kill her now but permissible to have killed her at an earlier age. The notion of "full moral status" as an ascertainable property is questioned and shown to be dependent on previously accepted …Read more
  •  149
    Sixteen days? A reply to B. Smith and B. Brogaard on the beginning of human individuals
    with Gregor Damschen and Dieter Schönecker
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 31 (2). 2006.
    When does a human being begin to exist? Barry Smith and Berit Brogaard have argued that it is possible, through a combination of biological fact and philosophical analysis, to provide a definitive answer to this question. In their view, a human individual begins to exist at gastrulation, i. e. at about sixteen days after fertilization. In this paper we argue that even granting Smith and Brogaard's ontological commitments and biological assumptions, the existence of a human being can be shown to …Read more
  •  19
    Using a Mindfulness-Based Intervention to Promote Subjective Well-Being, Trait Emotional Intelligence, Mental Health, and Resilience in Women With Fibromyalgia
    with Javier Cejudo, Francisco-Javier García-Castillo, Pablo Luna, Débora Rodrigo-Ruiz, and Roberto Feltrero
    Frontiers in Psychology 10. 2019.
  •  15
    Subjetividad y lenguaje en Freud y Lacan: del sujeto del inconsciente al giro pragmático de la filosofía
    Anales Del Seminario de Historia de la Filosofía 39 (2): 417-431. 2022.
    The following article presents an analysis of the conflict that occurs between philosophy and psychoanalysis in both the works of Sigmund Freud and Jacques Lacan; This conflict is conveyed from the alienated condition of the subject that arises from the thesis of the unconscious. The subject deconstructs himself as consciousness and reveals the impossibility of him in the very act in which he presents himself through his saying. In this way, language configures the Freudo-Lacanian idea of the un…Read more
  •  129
    From the geometric formulation of gravity, according to the Einstein-Grosmann-Hilbert equations, of November 1915, as the geodesic movement in the semirimennian manifold of positive curvature, spacetime, where due to absence of symmetries, the conservation of energy-impulse is not possible taking together the material processes and that of the gravitational geometric field, however, given those symmetries in the flat Minkowski spacetime, using the De Sitter model, Einstein linearizing gravitatio…Read more
  •  233
    From the geometric formulation of gravity, according to the Einstein-Grosmann-Hilbert equations, of November 1915, as the geodesic movement in the semirimennian manifold of positive curvature, spacetime, where due to absence of symmetries, the conservation of energy-impulse is not possible taking together the material processes and that of the gravitational geometric field, however, given those symmetries in the flat Minkowski spacetime, using the De Sitter model, Einstein linearizing gravitatio…Read more
  •  282
    Desde la formulación geométrica de la gravedad, según la ecuaciones de Einstein-Grosmann-Hilbert, de noviembre de 1915, como el movimiento geodésico en la variedad semirimenniana de curvatura positiva, espaciotiempo, donde por ausencias de simetrías, no es posible la conservación de la energía-impulso tomando en conjunto los procesos materiales y el del campo geométrico gravitacional, sin embargo, dadas esas simetrías en el espaciotiempo plano de Minkowski, usando el modelo de De Sitter, Einst…Read more